www.fgks.org   »   [go: up one dir, main page]

Excerpt of Sin

Page 1


SIN G R E G O RY M E L L E M A University of Notre Dame Press Notre Dame, Indiana

MELLEMA.indb 3

2/12/21 12:07 PM


Copyright © 2021 by University of Notre Dame Notre Dame, Indiana 46556 undpress.nd.edu All Rights Reserved Published in the United States of America

MELLEMA.indb 4

2/12/21 12:07 PM


CONTENTS

Preface Acknowledgments

one

Original and Inherited Sin

two

Individual and Collective Sins

11

three

Accessory Sins

21

four

Mortal versus Venial Sins

31

five

Supererogation and Sin

41

six

The Islamic Category of Acts That Are Discouraged

53

seven

Moral Ideals, Virtue Ethics, and Sin

63

eight

Sin and Symbolism

73

nine

Sin and the Problem of Evil

87

ten

Sin in Six Major World Religions

95

Notes Bibliography Index

MELLEMA.indb 7

ix xv

1

103 105 111

2/12/21 12:07 PM


Chapter one

ORIGINAL AND INHERITED SIN

This chapter concerns sin when it is taken to be a fundamental feature of the human condition. Understood in this manner, sin is not considered to be a property of people’s individual actions; rather, it is understood to be a property of the human condition in general. The most popular version of the idea that sin is a pervasive feature of the human condition is the doctrine of original sin and, in particular, the Augustinian account of original sin. The first section of this chapter surveys how this doctrine has been understood by various philosophers and by various religious traditions. The second section takes up the question of the noetic effects of sin. The third section deals with the question of whether the doctrine of original sin is unfair or unjust to those of us who are supposedly affected by it. The final section takes up the doctrine of primal sin, sin that had its origin prior to the existence of human beings, the theory of sin as uncleanness, and the doctrine of total depravity.

ORIGINAL SIN

The doctrine of original sin states that all human beings have been affected by sins committed by the earliest human beings. It is traditionally understood that these human beings were Adam, the first man, and Eve, the first woman, according to the story of their disobedience in Genesis 3. 1

MELLEMA.indb 1

2/12/21 12:07 PM


2  Original and Inherited Sin

This account of original sin is commonly referred to as the Augustinian account of original sin. According to Michael Rea, the doctrine of original sin was accepted by most of the medieval philosopher-theologians from Augustine through Duns Scotus. Moreover, it is affirmed by most of the creeds and confessions (post Athanasius) of the Orthodox, Roman Catholic, and evangelical Protestant churches. It is not, however, widely held by contemporary thinkers, in part because it appears to conflict with the intuitively plausible principle that person P is morally responsible for a state of affairs S obtaining only if S obtains (or obtained) and P could have prevented S from obtaining (Rea 2007, 310ff ). Although the Augustinian account has not had a great many advocates in the history of philosophy (at least since medieval times), it has had some. Philip Quinn argues that Kant, for example, though he rejects certain aspects of the Augustinian tradition, remains fairly close to it (Quinn 1990, 230). Five main elements compose the Augustinian doctrine of original sin, according to Jesse Couenhoven. First, original sin has as its source a first sin in the garden of Eden. Second, all of us share in this sin; the reason is that Adam was the progenitor of our race, and we have a solidarity with him. Third, all of us are born with an inherited sin, and this is the result of the first sin. It comes in two forms: common guilt and a constitutional fault (disordered desire and ignorance). Fourth, all human beings are ­subject to a penalty as the result of inherited sin; the penalty is that our powers are weakened and we die. Fifth, As Augustine speculated, sin and penalty are transmitted from one generation to the next (Couenhoven 2013, 23). These five elements are not all of equal status. The third is the conceptual heart of the doctrine of original sin. Although these five elements form a more or less affiliated body of subdoctrines, they do not rise or fall together. One could consistently affirm some and reject others. Michael Rea observes that there are different versions of the doctrine that goes by the name “original sin.” One states that all human beings (except for Adam, Eve, Jesus, and possibly his mother) suffer from a kind of corruption that makes it very likely that they will fall into sin. The ­second asserts that all human beings suffer from a kind of corruption that makes it inevitable that they will fall into sin, and this corruption is a consequence of the first sin of the first man. The third states that all human

MELLEMA.indb 2

2/12/21 12:07 PM


Original and Inherited Sin  3

beings are guilty from birth in the eyes of God, and this guilt is a consequence of the first sin of the first man (Rea 2007, 311). Eleonore Stump’s discussion of original sin begins with three propositions that she describes as Christian beliefs: (1) Adam fell, (2) natural evil (including moral evil) entered the world as a result of Adam’s fall, and (3) after death, depending on their state at the time of death, either (a) human beings go to heaven or (b) they go to hell (Stump 1985, 398). Stump believes that these propositions are especially relevant to the problem of evil. Stump concedes that these propositions will strike many people as implausible or just plain false. But she goes on to argue that although they are controversial and seem false to many people, they are not demonstrably false. To show that this is the case, she provides an interpretation of the doctrine of original sin that is not contradicted by the theory of evolution. Stump’s own interpretation of the doctrine of original sin is summarized by three propositions: (1) At some time in the past, as a result of their own choices, human beings altered their nature for the worse, (2) the alteration involved what we perceive and describe as a change in the nature of human free will, and (3) the changed nature of the will was inheritable (Stump 1985, 402–403). Stump asserts that these propositions are compatible with the denial that there was a particular man, Adam, who made a bad choice and fell from a better to a worse state because the past change in human nature need not have been due to a particular person (they are also compatible with the affirmation that it was Adam who made a bad choice). In addition, Stump contends that the theory of evolution does not entail the falsity of these propositions. It has often been stated that original sin (although not necessarily the Augustinian version) is the one theological doctrine that is capable of ­empirical verification. In his book Shanting Compound (1966) Langdon Gilkey describes his experiences in a prison camp. He states that the “unpadded” conditions there revealed human nature as it truly is, namely, with a fundamental inclination of the self toward its own welfare. Edward Langerak contends that Gilkey was here influenced by the “realist” ­theology of Reinhold Niebuhr (Langerak 2014, 22n1). Gilkey sees the ­behavior of prisoners in a prison camp as empirical verification of the doctrine of original sin.

MELLEMA.indb 3

2/12/21 12:07 PM


4  Original and Inherited Sin

Michael Ruse (2001) likewise believes that the doctrine is capable of empirical verification. He claims that Darwinian biology empirically supports it. According to him, self-interest runs rapidly into traits such as greed, lust, and boastfulness. There are good biological reasons for this, he says, because original sin is part of the biological package. In the Orthodox faith the term “original sin” refers to the first sin of Adam and Eve. As a result of this sin, humanity bears the consequences of sin, the chief of which is death. In western traditions, humanity likewise bears the consequences of sin. But the west also understands that humanity is guilty of the sin of Adam and Eve. In the Orthodox Christian understanding, while humanity does bear the consequences of the original sin, humanity does not bear the personal guilt associated with this sin. Adam and Eve were guilty of their willful action; we bear the consequences, chief of which is death. In the Orthodox faith, the term “ancestral sin” is sometimes used to reflect the belief that what is transmitted is not guilt. The remainder of this section will summarize the account of original sin furnished by the theology of the Roman Catholic Church. Catholic theology envisions original sin as a condition of being deprived of grace. The sin of Adam consists in the lack of sanctifying grace and signifies a turning away from God. Adam was the representative of the whole human race. On his voluntary decision depended either the preservation or the loss of the supernatural endowment, which was a gift to human nature as such. His sin was the sin of the whole human race (Ott 1955, 107ff ). Original sin is transmitted through the natural act of generation. The single sin of Adam is multiplied over and over through natural generation whenever a child of Adam is born. The soul created by God is good, according to its natural constitution. But God is not obliged to create the soul with the gift of sanctifying grace, and God is not to be blamed for creating new souls without a supernatural endowment. The blame rests with people who misused their freedom. Thus, in the state of original sin a person is deprived of sanctifying grace as well as the gifts of integrity. The lack of the gifts of integrity results in the human race’s being subject to concupiscence, suffering, and death. The person stained by original sin is in the imprisonment and slavery of the devil.

MELLEMA.indb 4

2/12/21 12:07 PM


Original and Inherited Sin  5

This condition should not be thought of as the complete corruption of human nature (in contrast to the view of the reformers). In the condition of original sin God’s creatures are able to know religious truths and perform morally good actions. Moreover, free will was not lost because of the sin of Adam. In baptism original sin is eradicated through the infusion of sanctifying grace. Those who depart this life while still in the state of original sin are excluded from the beatific vision of God. St. Thomas makes clear that those who depart this life with original sin alone deserve no punishment in addition to this exclusion. If any other punishment were inflicted, a person would be punished out of proportion to his guilt. His guilt did not arise from an action of his own, so he should not be punished by suffering himself. He loses only that which his nature was unable to obtain. In particular, children who die without baptism will not experience sorrow as the result of lacking such a grace (S.T., Appendix, I.Q.1). Catholic theologians usually assume that there is a special place or state for children who die without baptism, which they call limbus puerorum (limbo for children), although this is not part of Catholic doctrine.

THE EPISTEMOLOGICAL OR NOETIC EFFECTS OF SIN

Since the seventeenth century it has been widely believed that the doctrine of original sin has epistemological consequences. Pascal held that because all of us suffer from this malady, we wrongly perceived some of the most significant features of reality. Pascal’s prescription is natural ­theology, which he believes can be used to counteract the noetic effects of sin (Cuneo 1994, 646). Alvin Plantinga makes several claims about the noetic effects of sin. First, sin is in part an affective disorder or malfunction whereby our affections are pointed in the wrong direction. This disorder is presumably (given the context of the discussion) a malfunction of our cognitive faculties. Second, sin affects not only our knowledge of God but also our knowledge of ourselves and other people. Third, sin affects knowledge that is acquired by way of testimony. And, fourth, more indirectly, sin ­affects our knowledge of the world (Plantinga 2000, 206–213).

MELLEMA.indb 5

2/12/21 12:07 PM


6  Original and Inherited Sin

The examples given by Plantinga involving our knowledge of other people include thinking them inferior and misestimating or misunderstanding their attitudes toward us. For an example of sin affecting knowledge acquired by testimony, consider this: Suppose a sinful attitude on my part causes me to regard an acquaintance of mine as a liar. As a result, I might attach much less credulity to his testimony than I would if I lacked this sinful attitude. This attitude would then qualify as a noetic effect of sin because my presumption of his habitual lying would affect how I regarded his testimony. An example of sin affecting my knowledge of the world might be the following: A sinful attitude on my part might cause me to doubt many of the pronouncements of the scientific community, and as a result I might develop a distorted view of nature. I might judge that science is mistaken when it claims that the vaccinations that are routinely given to children do not cause autism. Or I might judge that science is mistaken when it claims that manmade global warming is taking place. Finally, as noted in the previous section, Couenhoven believes that Augustinian original sin can result in ignorance. By this I take him to mean that sin blinds us from the knowledge of certain truths about reality.

THE ALLEGED UNFAIRNESS OF THE DOCTRINE

People commonly allege that the doctrine of original sin is unfair: Since we are living thousands of years after Adam and Eve sinned, we are in no way morally responsible for what they did. How, then, can it be fair that we in some manner are affected by or held to account for what they did? There are several questions of unfairness that one might raise regarding original sin. Leibniz poses one in Confessio Philosophi: Couldn’t God have replaced Adam and Eve after their fall with better creatures, and wouldn’t this have prevented their sins from being transmitted to future generations? Leibniz (1699) answers this question by essentially saying that, if God had followed that course of action, a very different series of circumstances would have occurred, including different marriages, and

MELLEMA.indb 6

2/12/21 12:07 PM


Original and Inherited Sin  7

very different people would have been born. Therefore, we have no reason to be angry at God for allowing them to sin; our very existence depends on the toleration of their sins. Had they not been tolerated, people different from ourselves would have existed instead. Robert Merrihew Adams believes that Leibniz’s response to the unfairness question is correct (Adams 1987, 66). A person could easily have existed without some of the evils of the actual world (for example, future evils). But past evils that have profoundly affected the course of human history are different. Adams notes that his parents probably would not have met or married had it not been for World War I, and as a result he would not have been born. We might object that Leibniz has not solved the central unfairness issue. Recall Rea’s observation from section one that the doctrine of ­original sin appears to conflict with the intuitively plausible principle that ­person P is morally responsible for obtaining a state of affairs S only if S obtains (or obtained) and P could have prevented S from obtaining. The conflict Rea seems to have in mind is this: According to the Augustinian account of original sin, all of us have been affected by the sins of Adam and Eve and are hence morally responsible for obtaining the state of ­affairs of their sinning. But none of us has the ability to prevent this state of ­affairs from obtaining; hence, according to the principle cited by Rea, none of us is morally responsible for its obtaining. From this one might well conclude that it is unfair to hold us responsible for the sinful acts of Adam and Eve, so the doctrine of original sin should be rejected. In response, an advocate for the doctrine might defend a version of it different than what has traditionally been understood as the Augustinian account. Sometimes the sin that affects all members of the human race is described in terms of taint: Though we are not culpable, we are nevertheless tainted by the sins of Adam and Eve. According to this way of thinking, human beings can be tainted by the evil acts of others to whom they are connected in some significant manner. Although they are not culpable of these actions or their outcomes, their moral integrity is nevertheless affected (Appiah 1991, 229). Another way to describe what is essentially the same phenomenon is in terms of defilement, a symbolic stain (Ricoeur 1967, 35–37). According to this way of thinking, if we have been defiled by the sins of our original ancestors, the defilement takes the

MELLEMA.indb 7

2/12/21 12:07 PM


8  Original and Inherited Sin

form of a symbolic stain. Although the doctrine of original sin has been controversial for centuries, perhaps analyzing it in terms of taint or stain rather than culpability confers some plausibility on it. (Appiah’s views will be discussed in more detail in chapter 3). Consider once again the principle cited by Rea, the principle that a person is morally responsible for a state of affairs obtaining only if the person could have prevented it from happening. This principle no longer conflicts with the doctrine of original sin when it is understood in terms of moral taint. A proponent of this version of the doctrine can be happy to acknowledge that we are not morally responsible for the sinful be­havior of Adam and Eve. We are merely tainted by their sinful behavior. The responsibility part of the doctrine no longer applies.

PRIMAL SIN, SIN AS UNCLEANNESS, AND TOTAL DEPRAVITY

This section contains additional views about sin that fall under the rubric of sin understood as a fundamental feature of the human condition. Primal Sin

In addition to original sin there is a phenomenon called primal sin, the sin of the angels who freely rebelled against God. Augustine regards the stories of creaturely falls in scripture to consist of free choices that have resulted in the origins of evil. The sins of Adam and Eve in the garden gave rise to original sin, while evil free choices on the part of angels account for primal sin. Primal sin preceded the sins of Adam and Eve. Augustine regarded the serpent in the story of Adam and Eve’s fall as having been used by the devil and regarded the devil as a fallen angel. Scott MacDonald points out that the sins of the angels deserve to be called primal not just because they preceded the sins of human beings but also because they constituted something new in creation (MacDonald 1999, 110). The first evil, says MacDonald, appears against a backdrop of total goodness. Everything created by God is wholly good and without defect, and this includes the creatures with rationality who freely choose evil.

MELLEMA.indb 8

2/12/21 12:07 PM


Original and Inherited Sin  9

Sin as Uncleanness

Marilyn McCord Adams argues that sin, at its most basic level, is uncleanness. As such, it is an outgrowth of two metaphysical roots (Adams 1999, 94). The first metaphysical root is the metaphysical gap. The so-called size gap between ourselves and God misfits us for each other’s company. Humans are flimsy, temporary, and vulnerable to attack from all sorts of things, and nothing we could naturally be or do would make us suitable for God’s company. Because God and creatures are so radically different in kind, it is difficult to see how God and humans could ever occupy the same social world. The second metaphysical root is metaphysical straddling. Human nature seems unclean in itself because it is not simply one kind or another. The heterogeneity of human nature is sometimes conceptualized as soul and body, spirit and matter, or personal and animal. Traditional anthropologies see the material corporeal and animal distracting the mind’s cognitive and evaluative attention and luring it into preferring lesser goods to greater. At the same time, mind interferes with matter, trying to impose its own agenda. The human straddles the spiritual and the material and thus is neither one kind nor the other. Total Depravity

The Augustinian doctrine of original sin has led many to embrace a doctrine known as total depravity. The doctrine of total depravity states that human beings are so corrupt that they are unable to do any good and are inclined toward all evil. Many adherents of this doctrine go on to believe that if and only if human beings are born again are they capable of rising out of this dire condition. But left to their own devices, human beings are helpless to escape this condition of all-encompassing sin and depravity. The doctrine of original sin does not entail the doctrine of total depravity. After all, being tainted by Adam’s sin doesn’t entail that one is totally incapable of good works. But two Reformed confessional statements of the sixteenth century, the 1562 Belgic Confession and the 1563

MELLEMA.indb 9

2/12/21 12:07 PM


10  Original and Inherited Sin

­ eidelberg Catechism, link them together in such a way as to suggest that H the one follows quite naturally from the other. Finally, related to total depravity is the notion of transworld depravity, which was introduced by Alvin Plantinga in his account of the free will defense. Plantinga’s definition of transworld depravity is quite lengthy and complex, but the basic idea, according to Paul Tidman, is this: “Moral agents suffer from transworld deparavity if they are such that if they were created they would go wrong with respect to at least one moral choice. The core of the Free Will Defense is the claim that it is possible that no matter who God created it was true that they would have performed at least some wrong actions” (Tidman 2008, 400). Suppose that a possible creature (one that exists in at least some possible world) is such that if he were to exist in the actual world he would sin at least once. Then, according to Tidman’s formulation of Plantinga’s definition, this possible creature would suffer from transworld depravity. The notion of transworld depravity will be discussed in greater detail in chapter 9.

MELLEMA.indb 10

2/12/21 12:07 PM


Issuu converts static files into: digital portfolios, online yearbooks, online catalogs, digital photo albums and more. Sign up and create your flipbook.