www.fgks.org   »   [go: up one dir, main page]

Excerpt from Reason and Politics

Page 1


REASON AND

POLITICS The Nature of Political Phenomena

MARK BLITZ

University of Notre Dame Press Notre Dame, Indiana

BLITZ.indb 3

10/14/20 3:22 PM


Contents

Introduction 1 one

The Nature of Practical Action

11

t wo

The Nature of Freedom and Rights

33

t h r e e The Nature of Power and Property

69

f o u r The Nature of Virtue

96

five

The Nature of What Is Common

115

six

The Nature of Goods

133

Conclusion

157

Notes 163 Index 187

BLITZ.indb 7

10/14/20 3:22 PM


Introduction

This book’s subject is the nature of basic political phenomena such as freedom, justice, and the common good. I wish to explore and clarify these phenomena but do not intend my effort to lead directly to practical results. I share the classical view that political phenomena are the heart of human affairs and central to understanding much that is not usually considered political. If we truly stand on the brink of transforming human nature it is especially important to illuminate what we seek to transform and what we may gain or lose in the effort. I intend my study to contribute to this clarification.1 To explore the nature of political phenomena is equivalent to exploring what is reasonable about them. “Nature” is the correlative of reason. It is what reason seeks to know about things, a view that begins with the classics and is still visible when we call the truths of physics and economics natural laws. I intend to examine the degree to which what we can uncover reasonably about political phenomena is not an adjunct to them but, rather, forms and directs them. The “nature” of something is what in it we do not produce, what is common or pervasive in it, and what is essential to it. Our everyday use of the term attests to this. “Nature” is the environment and the species we do not make, and to be “natural” is to be spontaneous, not artificial and affected. Someone is said to have a calm or excitable nature, a characteristic that pervades his actions and is always present. The “nature” of something is its essence, what is always there that is important, not trivial, and that forms the thing’s other characteristics. 1

BLITZ.indb 1

10/14/20 3:22 PM


2 Introduction

Something’s nature, therefore, also distinguishes it, as speech distinguishes us from cats. This is not to say that the connection between what we make and do not make is transparent, that how characteristics can be common or pervasive is obvious, or that how essential characteristics function is clear.2 It is to say that the natural as what is unmade, general, and essential is what reason qua reason seeks to know. Reason concerns primarily what we do not perceive physically, seeks what is general or universal, and separates and combines matters chiefly according to their central characteristics. As I said, reason is oriented to what is natural. It may seem odd to seek what is naturally true about politics because politics is so conventional, structured by laws that we enact, dealing with passing circumstances, and variable in different places and times. Nonetheless, political life serves an understanding of what can be good, pursued by actions that are more or less just.3 If what is good and just are natural and reason can know them, politics need not and, indeed, cannot be irredeemably conventional. Politics involves what belongs to me and to us, as well as what is good or just simply. It involves what is particular and impure, however general. It involves freedom, passions, force, and prudence. The point, then, is to explore these matters in terms of how they are formed and directed by speech or reason, our unmade, pervasive, and essential characteristic. My goal is to bring out what is rational in what is contingent, or not simply rational, in us.4 The attempt to understand political life reasonably inevitably falls short. Matters are too complex to allow this attempt to succeed completely. One of my goals is to clarify the reasons for this complexity and for disputability in judgment and choice. We cannot measure all good things, including our own freedom, on a single scale. Nonetheless, we can judge matters reasonably, primarily in relation to the completeness of the use of our human powers. Another goal I have is to consider rivals to my argument. One rival is the view that only what is mechanistic and mathematical about us is strictly speaking true. I will discuss this when I discuss freedom. The other is that reason itself is inherently contingent and particular. I will discuss this “historicist” view at various points in the book.

BLITZ.indb 2

10/14/20 3:22 PM


Introduction 3

The Importance of Political Phenomena

Imagine that theoretical, philosophical, scientific, academic, and theological ways of understanding did not exist. How do they originate? In what phenomena are they rooted, and what calls for theoretical discussion? How do intellectual analyses still rely on and refer back to the phenomena from which they emerge? We recognize, of course, that these ways to understand do exist now. Indeed, they often make it difficult to see clearly the basic phenomena from which they emerge.5 We deal with terms such as “freedom,” “property,” “power,” “justice,” and “pleasure” as if they have always been matters of studied reflection. The variety in intellectual views, moreover, causes disputes that also block access to phenomena. Who today can look clearly at the relations between men and women, at whether human differences suggest basic inequalities, or at whether some activities are genuinely better than others? Who, taking such a look, feels free to say what he thinks? The twin results of our ­obfuscations—passive relativism and self-righteous self-interest—are visible, if themselves difficult to discuss honestly. These obfuscations also make it important to uncover basic phenomena clearly, including the possibilities of disagreement about them. Otherwise, they are lost to common understanding and to reflection. We must also try to clarify the basic political phenomena because of the questions we face technologically: the growth of artificial intelligence and the effort to reduce everything human to the molecular and mathematical, perhaps, indeed, in order to make us over. Academics often discuss the distinctively human in terms of “consciousness” and relate these scientific elements to it. This points to the issue. But it also distorts it, for “consciousness” is already a remote way to approach what is human. It is a particular understanding that stems from a modern theoretical approach.6 I will instead attempt to show that the original context of our activities is the political community, our involvement in common matters. Isolation of human characteristics, including who “I” am stems from this involvement. Exploring basic political phenomena is the first step in understanding human ­affairs.

BLITZ.indb 3

10/14/20 3:22 PM


4 Introduction

The Political and the Cosmopolitan

Although the political contexts that form human phenomena are central to how we first see and deal with them, we must also account for what seems to be beyond political context, or cosmopolitan. A context’s elements are suffused by the whole and are not merely detachable parts. Political actions and institutions in liberal democracies, for example, belong to the entire regime. One should not think of a country’s institutions or laws as if they are simply separable from it and could be the same anywhere. Ignoring this often causes failed political reform. Nonetheless, a context’s elements are not meaningful merely as its parts and nothing but its parts, with no possible independence. This is clear with physical and living objects such as trees and animals, which appear the same in democracies and oli­ garchies, in Athens and Berlin. Whatever the complexities involved here—stars that some view as gods, for example, species of trees that are unseen by most because they dwell on an aristocrat’s estate, or animals unusable for unholy purposes—it is hard to deny that the tree noticed in one kingdom, its shape and natural reproduction, is largely the same as in others.7 Consider now courage and moderation. More clearly than with living and physical things, these differ with political context. Is it moderate to eschew the unholy allure of pleasure in order to stay on a righteous religious path? Or, rather, is it moderate to deal properly with pleasure considered as a good that inspires continued accumulation? Or is moderation, as proper enjoyment, noble in itself? These different views are connected to different political contexts and opinions about justice. They belong together with related views of piety, pride, freedom, and property. To what degree, however, can we nonetheless discover what is similar in these different instances of moderation? Is there not some comparability in pleasure as we seek, experience, and moderately control it, and in fear and courageously directing it, whether the control belongs to righteousness, bourgeois calculation, or classical nobility? To the degree this comparability exists we can consider each virtue on its own apart from its context and compare and perhaps even judge or rank its instances. In discuss-

BLITZ.indb 4

10/14/20 3:22 PM


Introduction 5

ing basic phenomena I will explore the interplay between the dependence of phenomena on the whole or context to which they belong and the degree of independence that allows each to be addressed in its own terms. This interplay is the essence of human experience.8

How to Begin

My purpose is to clarify the nature of basic political phenomena. One problem arises immediately: how to begin? But is this problem not preceded by the question of why we should engage in the inquiry at all? A search for a missing suspect begins with clarity about who is missing and about why one seeks to find him, places to begin to look, and what counts as a successful result. If we do not know how to begin, perhaps our inquiry is unnecessary. Presumably, we are unclear about basic political phenomena: the path to understanding and its beginning are connected to dispelling this initial unclarity. In what way are we unclear? For us today, unclarity on matters such as freedom and the common good is related to the complexity of our way of life, to our political partisanship, and to the variety of intellectual doctrines that we teach. What freedom is, is unclear because we dispute it politically and intellectually. What, then, would end dispute or count as clarity? What would count as success? The questions of clarity and success, however, are themselves embedded in something still more original. For these questions are intelligible to us in some way. This original intelligibility is obvious when we look for a missing suspect (or a lost wallet) because there the intelligibility of losing, searching, and finding belongs to ­evident contexts of activity—to crime and punishment or to using everyday implements. The initial intelligibility within which unclarity about basic phenomena lies is the first clue to their meaning, because how we state and experience questions, unclarity, and the approach to dispelling them is embedded in this intelligibility.9 Perhaps, however, even “intelligibility” is disputed and unclear. Indeed it is, among philosophers. Martin Heidegger discusses ordinary intelligibility in terms of what allows us to understand how anything is at all. Plato connects our partially clear opinions to the true

BLITZ.indb 5

10/14/20 3:22 PM


6 Introduction

basis of intelligibility, his “ideas.” Hegel displays the intelligibility of things through our step-by-step dialectical movement to what is completely and Absolutely so. Hobbes grounds facts on the experience of our senses, and on agreement about the names we use to ­designate things.10 The conflicting ways to ground intelligibility also indicate why a possibly indubitable or certain beginning may not be the correct starting point. For searching for and recognizing such a beginning also depends on a notion of intelligibility that we can challenge. And it is not evident that certainty is the appropriate goal for truly understanding the matters we are studying. At some point what thinkers uncover must account for their own activities and discoveries. But when they begin they cannot start from their own completed views. Nor can they give evidence for their views or expect us to consider them true without confronting the o ­ rdinarily meaningful and intelligible. The most arcane physics indicates its truth about more than its own constructs by showing its useful or ­destructive effects in the ordinary world. My own inquiry concerns political phenomena, moreover, and these belong to every­day life.11

Ordinary Understanding and Political Concepts

For these reasons, I will begin from ordinary understanding and intelligibility. But which ordinary understanding? One characteristic of thought from Nietzsche forward is the attempt to root science, philosophy, art, and morality in a ground more basic than these activities themselves, yet not a physical-materialistic ground to which we can reduce everything. It is not mathematical physics alone that is fundamental but something equally or more central in which science itself is rooted. This effort is behind the “life philosophy” and radical historicism that follow Nietzsche. It leads to Husserl’s discussion of intentionality and the lifeworld, to discussions of the so-called natural world, standpoint, or horizon, and, especially, to Heidegger’s analysis in Being and Time of human “being-in-the-world.”12 Although this

BLITZ.indb 6

10/14/20 3:22 PM


Introduction 7

effort culminates first in Heidegger’s early analyses, it does not rest there. It continues next in Heidegger’s further thought, and in that of his and Husserl’s students, notably Leo Strauss and Jacob Klein. Problems such as the origin of philosophy, political philosophy, and modern mathematics are examined with Husserl’s phenomenological standpoint and some of Heidegger’s discoveries in mind.13 The result of these discussions is to recognize the importance or inevitability of beginning not from supposedly timeless yet in fact ­inherited concepts but, rather, from one’s own immersion in one’s own world.14 Still, this beginning does not presume that thought must remain relative to one’s time and place. To begin from immersion in our own world is to begin from immersion in intelligible things and activities. This is less obvious than it seems. Some argue, instead, that we must begin from sense data, or material certainties.15 This view is challenged powerfully by Heidegger, who argues, instead, that the things we uncover in significant worlds are as much as the material characteristics that seem to produce them. One of his best-known examples is our immersion in working with tools, such that each step is involved with the others and all are generally “ready to hand.” Ready to hand entities are no less than the merely neutral ones we discover scientifically, from which they might seem to derive. A second example is his notion that a mood such as fear releases entities in their fearsomeness and that we cannot reduce their being as fearful to the merely chemical or physiological.16 In Heidegger’s view, our defining human characteristics are precisely those involved in our immersion in everyday worlds, and in the projection of possibilities that allows this. Heidegger’s understanding, however, is not the only attempt to begin from things as we deal with them. This beginning also characterizes Plato and Aristotle, something that Heidegger’s standpoint and his approach to them help us to recognize.17 I will attempt to develop our everyday beginning with attention to classical arguments in particular. I will orient my discussion to my theme: the substance of basic political phenomena.18 But the need to begin from things as we deal with them, our reliance on ordinary practical intelligibility,

BLITZ.indb 7

10/14/20 3:22 PM


8 Introduction

shows the importance of grounding all our concepts in ordinary ­contexts and ultimately, I will argue, in political ways of life.

How to Proceed

I will therefore start from our immersion in our own world and try to tease out from contemporary examples and directions the structural characteristics that comprise being immersed within an activity. My purpose is, first, to explore how human experience depends on context. It is, next, to show how particular activities and contexts belong to something common or whole that is characterized largely by the understanding of justice or righteousness that forms a way of life. Concretely, this means life within a political regime such as a liberal democracy or classical aristocracy or an orthodox religious way. Justice, moreover, embodies and serves an understanding of happiness, excellence, what is good, and what is appropriate. I will therefore explore how ways of life—political wholes—are constituted by how things first meaningfully approach us as choiceworthy, together with the justice that forms us. Each of our experiences comes to light within a meaningful activity; contexts that form meaningful action are linked by a political way of life; and the most significant political phenomena order, define, and are the central substance of this way of life and, consequently, these contexts.19 The coherence of contexts is not an intellectual superstructure we place over experience but is inherent in experience itself. Nonetheless, however close knit a way of life, it cannot encapsulate experience fully. As I suggested, we can observe moderation and courage somewhat apart from the orders within which we practice them. This separate view of the excellence of a regime’s parts also allows us to question the justice and view of goodness that constitute it as a whole. This exploration, in turn, permits fuller understanding of the parts, the phenomena that belong to the regime. This dialectic or spiral of the closedness of a way of life and openness to what is independent from it indicates the complexity of human experience, and the possibility of exploring matters theoretically.

BLITZ.indb 8

10/14/20 3:22 PM


Introduction 9

Once explicit thought emerges we can see that basic political phenomena involve not only everyday intelligibility but also general and abstract matters. To comprehend practical affairs we must sometimes push forward to an understanding of ends, wholes, independence, movement, and other matters that we usually address philosophically. A community’s parts, for example, can be common or separate in several forms: citizens can be identical, or they can vary by class. Good things can satisfy or complete in different ways. I mean to explore the place of several of these issues in understanding political phenomena. Much “abstract” understanding, in turn, generalizes from political opinion and experience. The place of theoretical issues is especially salient in liberal democracy, given our explicit basis in a notion of natural rights articulated by John Locke and other thinkers.20 I will concentrate on the meaning of practice, freedom, rights, power, property, virtue, goods, common goods, and justice. Because these phenomena are interlocking, I will discuss each in several places and not only in the chapter or section chiefly devoted to it. I will also address other topics that are salient to my arguments or appear to counter them. Among these are the natural basis of history, religion, and innovation; the relation between what is good and one’s own; the possibility of ranking and comparing ways of life; and the place of reason in experiencing the passions.

BLITZ.indb 9

10/14/20 3:22 PM


Issuu converts static files into: digital portfolios, online yearbooks, online catalogs, digital photo albums and more. Sign up and create your flipbook.