www.fgks.org   »   [go: up one dir, main page]

Academia.eduAcademia.edu
181 [Corry Shores, “Body and World in Merleau-Ponty and Deleuze,” Studia Phaenomenologica XII (2012): 181–209. This is a pre-publication draft that has been repaginated to match that of the print version.] Body and World in Merleau-Ponty and Deleuze 1 Corry Shores University of Leuven Abstract: To compare Merleau-Ponty’s and Deleuze’s phenomenal bodies, I first examine how for Merleau-Ponty phenomena appear on the basis of three levels of integration: 1) between the parts of the world, 2) between the parts of the body, and 3) between the body and its world. I contest that Deleuze’s attacks on phenomenology can be seen as constructive critiques rather than as being expressions of an anti-phenomenological position. By building from Deleuze’s definition of the phenomenon and from his more phenomenologically relevant writings, we find that phenomena for him are given to the body under exactly the opposite conditions as for Merleau-Ponty, namely that 1) the world’s differences 2) appear to a disordered body that 3) comes into shocking affective contact with its surroundings. I argue that a Deleuzian theory of bodily-given phenomena is better suited than Merleau-Ponty’s model in the task of accounting for the intensity of phenomenal appearings. Keywords: Deleuze, Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology, Body, World 1. Introduction As Joe Hughes observes, there is “not much consensus in the current critical literature when it comes to the question of Deleuze’s relationship to phenomenology.” 2 On the one hand, Deleuze is often explicitly critical of Husserl, Merleau-Ponty, and phenomenology in general, and many commentators have regarded those critiques as expressing an antiphenomenological tendency in Deleuze’s thinking. 3 Other scholars acknowledge the tensions 1 May I thank Roland Breeur, Ullrich Melle, and Nicolas de Warren of the Husserl Archives in Leuven for their contributions to this paper. 2 J. Hughes, Deleuze and the Genesis of Representation, London: Continuum, 2008, p. 3. 3 See, for example, M. Foucault, “Theatrum Philosophicum,” in D. Bouchard (ed.), Language, Counter-Memory, Practice: Selected Essays and Interviews, English trans. by D. Bouchard and S. Simon, Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1977, pp. 165–196; L. Lawlor, “The End of Phenomenology: Expressionism in Deleuze and Merleau-Ponty,” Continental Philosophy Review 31.1 (1998), pp. 15–34; D. Olkowski, Deleuze and the Ruin of Representation, Berkeley: University of California Press, 1999; L. Lawlor, Thinking through French Philosophy: The Being of the Question, Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2003; D. Olkowski, “Philosophy of Structure, Philosophy of Event: Deleuze’s Critique of Phenomenology,” Chiasmi International 13 (2011), pp. 193–216; and P. Montebello, “Deleuze, une anti-phénoménologie?” Chiasmi International 13 (2011), pp. 315– 325. 182 between Deleuze and phenomenology while also recognizing fundamental compatibilities, as well as the ways that Deleuze’s critiques fail to grasp the ambiguities and later development of Merleau-Ponty’s thinking. 4 Some scholars have gone so far as to suggest that Deleuze’s ideas can be seen as a radicalization of phenomenology. 5 According to Alain Beaulieu, Deleuze thrived on his conflictual relation with phenomenology. For Deleuze, phenomenology is an enemy of sorts that benefited him like a friend, because it helped him advance his own ideas. 6 Our analysis here, however, is interested not so much in what was the relationship of Deleuze’s ideas to phenomenology, but more in what it could become when we treat his criticisms as constructive critiques. Might it be possible to do phenomenology in a Deleuzean way? Miguel de Beistegui writes: Has phenomenology not characterized itself throughout precisely as this ability to become and evolve? And is this not the historical lesson of phenomenology: that it is itself a flow, with unpredictable bends and meanderings, which, whatever their intensity, in the end always reinvent phenomenology […]. […] there is no “letter” of phenomenology: no primordial word, no consecrated text, no originary truth that one could betray: only an endless series of heresies, which is, at least in philosophy, the only possible form of fidelity, that is, the fidelity in and through genuine questioning. 7 We will place Deleuze’s philosophy of the body without organs, then, in stark contrast to Merleau-Ponty’s integrationist model to show that Deleuze’s 4 See, for example, C. Boundas, “Translator’s Introduction: Deleuze, Empiricism, and the Struggle for Subjectivity,” in G. Deleuze, Empiricism and Subjectivity: An Essay on Hume’s Theory of Human Nature, English trans. by C. Boundas, New York: Columbia University Press, 1991, pp. 1–19; J. Reynolds and J. Roffe, “Deleuze and Merleau-Ponty: Immanence, Univocity and Phenomenology,” Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 37.3 (2006), pp. 229–251; H. Somers-Hall, “Deleuze and Merleau-Ponty: Aesthetics of Difference,” in C. Boundas (ed.), Deleuze: The Intensive Reduction, London: Continuum, 2009, pp. 123–130; J. Hughes, op. cit.; J. Wambacq, “Depth and Time in Merleau-Ponty and Deleuze,” Chiasmi International 13 (2011), pp. 327–348; J. Wambacq, “Maurice Merleau-Ponty and Gilles Deleuze as Interpreters of Henri Bergson,” in A. Tymieniecka (ed.), Transcendentalism Overturned: From Absolute Power of Consciousness until the Forces of Cosmic Architectonics (Analecta Husserliana 108), Dordrecht: Springer, 2011, pp. 269–284; and J. Wambacq, “Maurice Merleau-Ponty’s Criticism on Bergson’s Theory of Time Seen Through the Work of Gilles Deleuze,” Studia Phaenomenologica 11 (2011), pp. 309–325. 5 See, for example, C. Colebrook, Gilles Deleuze, London: Routledge, 2002; L. Bryant, Difference and Givenness: Deleuze’s Transcendental Empiricism and the Ontology of Immanence, Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 2008. 6 A. Beaulieu, Gilles Deleuze et la phénoménologie, Mons: Sils Maria, 2004. 7 M. Beistegui, “Toward a Phenomenology of Difference?” Research in Phenomenology 30 (2000), p. 68. 183 conception is better suited for explaining the intensities of phenomena. To do this, we first examine how phenomena appear to Merleau-Ponty on account of three coordinated levels of integrations, namely, the integration between the parts of the world, the integration of our body parts, and our body’s integration within its phenomenal world. Then parallel to each level we find contrary principles in our Deleuzian theory of the phenomenological body: for Deleuze, phenomena would appear when our body, whose parts are working disjunctively, detects incompatible differences in a surrounding world that is split off from it during a shocking encounter. 2. Phenomenal Integration For Merleau-Ponty we never perceive qualities or other parts of perception purely in themselves, but rather only in their integrated relation with other qualities or parts. He has us imagine a white patch on a homogeneous background. No matter what we are looking at, there will always be something surrounding it. If in our example we are looking in the middle at a particular point, we thereby sense it belonging together among its neighboring parts, with all these points belonging to the whole patch. Or if we see a part of the patch at the boundary, we also thereby sense it belonging with the neighboring parts of the patch but not with the adjacent points outside it in the background. 8 So already we see there is no such thing as a purely atomic perception. In fact, all the nearby qualities are influencing the way any part of something looks: This red patch which I see on the carpet is red only in virtue of a shadow which lies across it, its quality is apparent only in relation to the play of light upon it, and hence as an element in a spatial configuration. Moreover the colour can be said to be there only if it occupies an area of a certain size, too small an area not being describable in these terms. 9 We are also misled into thinking that there is a “point-by-point” constant correspondence between the parts of what we see and the parts of our “elementary perception.” 10 Certain optical illusions disprove this thesis. Fig. 1 One part of the Müller-Lyer illusion 8 M. Merleau-Ponty, Phénoménologie de la perception, Paris: Gallimard, 1945, p. 9; Phenomenology of Perception, English trans. by C. Smith, London: Routledge, 1962, pp. 3–4. Henceforth abbreviated as PP, with French/English page numbers. 9 PP, p. 10/4. 10 PP, p. 14/7. 184 Consider for example the above portion of the Müller-Lyer optical illusion [figure 1]. We see two equal lines. Now, view the remaining pieces [figure 2]. Fig. 2 Another part of the Müller-Lyer illusion When we put them together [figure 3], we do not see them combined into two equal lines with inverted arrow-ends. Fig. 3 Müller-Lyer illusion Rather, the horizontal lines now appear as bearing different lengths, on account of their integrated relations with the angled pieces. Hence, what we sense is not the immediate effect of the parts making one-to-one impressions on us: normal functioning must be understood as a process of integration in which the text of the external world is not so much copied as composed. And if we try to seize ‘sensation’ within the perspective of the bodily phenomena which pave the way to it, we find […] a formation already bound up with a larger whole […]. […] the perceived, by its nature, admits of the ambiguous, the shifting, and is shaped by its context. 11 The integration of phenomenal parts has for Merleau-Ponty a certain phenomenological structure, namely, the horizonal structure of our intentional awareness. The red of the stain on the carpet has its particular look on account of the other qualities and objects expressing themselves in that appearance, for example, the overlaying shadow that tinges the color. So when we see the red, our minds are also made aware of the blanket of shade covering the area, even if we are not explicitly aware of it. We will not be surprised when we look up and see something blocking the light source. The red’s particular shaded look refers our mind to something not explicit in the perception. Our minds have an awareness of it, but it is not in the forefront of our attention. As an implied phenomenon, it hovers at the edges of our awareness, which could literally be the perimeter of our field of vision or just be a vague, indeterminate, and 11 PP, pp. 16/9, 18/11. 185 ambiguous part of our intentional consciousness, residing in the background of what our minds are currently attending to. It looms on the “horizon” of our awareness. To see red, then, means that this red announces something else which it does not include, that it exercises a cognitive function, and that its parts together make up a whole to which each is related without leaving its place. Henceforth the red is no longer merely there, it represents something for me, and what it represents is not possessed as a ‘real part’ of my perception, but only aimed at as an ‘intentional part’. 12 Because each elementary part of our perception “arouses the expectation of more than it contains,” it is “therefore already charged with a meaning”; 13 it is already indicating or suggesting some other phenomenon. In fact, this horizonal integration of phenomenal objects is so involved that to see one object from a given perspective is also to have on the horizon of our awareness the way that object looks from the perspectives of every other object facing it. Merleau-Ponty illustrates this effectively with the arm-shadow in Rembrandt’s De Nachtwacht [figure 4]. 14 Fig. 4 Rembrandt’s De Nachtwacht (The Night Watch) 15 12 PP, p. 20/13. PP, p. 9/4. 14 M. Merleau-Ponty, “L’œil et l’esprit,” in C. Lefort (ed.), Œuvres, Paris: Gallimard, 2010, p. 1599; “Eye and Mind,” English trans. by C. Dallery, in J. M. Edie (ed.), The Primacy of Perception and Other Essays, Evanston: Northwestern University Press, p. 167. Henceforth abbreviated as OE, with French/English page numbers. 15 This image and the following details: Rembrandt, De Nachtwacht, Wikimedia Commons, http://commons.wikimedia.org/wiki/File:Rembrandt_nightwatch_large.jpg, accessed 14-Dec-2011. 13 186 Notice how the man in the foreground holds out his arm, which casts a shadow on the man standing next to him [figures 5 and 6]. Figs. 5 and 6 Details from Rembrandt’s De Nachtwacht We do not merely see his arm from just our perspective; we also see it as if we were looking from his right side at the angle of the light source, because the shadow we see from our perspective presents to us the appearance of his arm from the sun’s perspective. This illustration will help us grasp the sort of panoptic vision we have even from our glance at one viewpoint. Consider also when we stand between a set of railroad tracks and look down their straight extent into the distance. They seem to converge very far off. But this tells us they must be still parallel all the way in the distance, because they would instead appear parallel from here only if they continually diverged as they progressed. In a way, seeing the convergence is to indirectly stand far down the tracks and view them being parallel. 16 Yet, this means we are implicitly taking the perspective of horizonally implied objects related to the one in focus: every object is the mirror of all others. When I look at the lamp on my table, I attribute to it […] the qualities […] which the chimney, the walls, the table can ‘see’; but back of my lamp is nothing but the face which it ‘shows’ to the chimney. I can therefore see an object in so far as objects form a system or a world, and in so far as each one treats the others round it as spectators of its hidden aspects […]. Any seeing of an object by me is instantaneously reiterated among all those objects in the world which are apprehended as co-existent […]. 17 Merleau-Ponty offers another illustration to help us grasp just how thoroughly different phenomena are horizonally integrated. He has us consider when we view the tiled floor at the bottom of a pool of water. We might think that we are seeing the geometry of the tiles despite the wavy distortions that 16 17 OE, p. 1624/187. PP, pp. 82–83/68. 187 the water produces. Yet, really the floor, as the appearance that it happens to be, is seeable only because it is given to us through the rippling water. We should not assume there is such a thing as an object seen in itself. All things are sensed in their intermeshment with everything else. Even the water we mentioned is not contained only there in the pool. When we raise our eyes to the trees above the water, we see the webbed play of the water’s reflections. The tree foliage has its particular appearance only because the water below it “sends into it, upon it its active and living essence.” 18 Yet, because these horizonal objects are indeterminate and ambiguous, we are motivated to turn our attention toward them, which then makes them determinate. To better understand this process, Merleau-Ponty refers us to the way that children acquire the ability to perceive distinct colors. At first, they can only distinguish colored things from non-colored things. Then, they differentiate warm and cool shades of colored regions. Finally, they can discern different colors. The psychologist mistakenly thinks that the child originally perceived the different specific colors in their determinacy, except the child was merely unaware of the colors’ identities. So according to this psychological interpretation, children first can see the redness of the red, with its difference to the blueness of blue, but they just have not yet learned the corresponding names and concepts for the color. Merleau-Ponty says that instead the colors were originally seen in an indeterminate form, and only gradually does the child come to constitute them distinctly. In other words, the child sees different colors but not so much the distinctions between them, although these differences hang implicitly on the horizon of her awareness. 19 There are relations, then, between the colors that are seen, although they appear only implicitly. So, when children early on see neighboring things bearing different colors, they have a vague sense that the visual appearances differ in some significant way. After later learning how to detect the differences between the colors, they then see them determinately and uniquely. Because the colors began indeterminately, their becoming a determinate appearance was merely on the horizon of the child’s awareness. We might here notice another sort of horizon. The determinate forms were there indirectly in the beginning stage. Yet, their arrival to the child’s consciousness is pending; in a way, it hangs on a sort of temporal horizon too, being at the edge of the grasp of the present intentions. The parts of our phenomenal world are given so pre-integrated that even when the world suddenly appears to us quite differently than the moment before, in a way we were already anticipating the alteration. 20 He depicts a scene to illustrate. We walk along a shoreline. Before us is a ship run aground in the beach. Behind it is a forest, and the ship’s masts blend in with the trees, preventing us from initially noticing them as belonging to the ship. Yet, there 18 OE, p. 1616/182. PP, p. 38/29–30. 20 PP, p. 23/15. 19 188 will come a moment when we feel that the look of some of the trees is on the verge of altering. Before even seeing the masts as distinct from the forest, we felt some sort of tension in their appearance, just as “a storm is imminent in storm clouds.” 21 Even when originally mistaken, we still perceived all the distinguishing qualities of the masts, and they told us indirectly they were not trees. So from the beginning we had a “vague expectation” that there was something more to be understood in the appearance of the forest: The unity of the object is based on the foreshadowing of an imminent order which is about to spring upon us a reply to the questions merely latent in the landscape. It solves a problem set only in the form of a vague feeling of uneasiness, it organizes elements which up to that moment did not belong to the same universe and which, for that reason, […] could not be associated. 22 So whenever the phenomenal composition of our world changes, it is because we turn our attention to some detail that alters the way we configure the whole. We were motivated to turn our attention in the direction of other phenomenal parts; so in the case of the ship and forest, at the edges of our awareness we sensed some details that told us there was something questionable about certain trees. Only afterward did we learn that these details were indications that the trees were really ship masts instead. So in other words, even though we might have these dramatic experiences where the phenomenal world around us radically rearranges before our eyes, it does not involve a complete incoherence from one moment to the next; the new, altered world was somehow still there on the horizon of our awareness, if only as the suggestion that there is more to be seen. In fact, it is only because it was there on the horizon that we were motivated to discover it. This holds as well in Merleau-Ponty’s account of children’s acquisition of color sense. Once they learn how to discern different colors from one another, there is “a change of the structure of consciousness, the establishment of a new dimension of experience, the setting forth of an a priori.” 23 So, children lose the ability to see colors in that indeterminate way they appeared in early childhood. It would seem then that they find themselves in a new world that is incoherent with the prior one now hovering marginally in their retentional consciousness, from back when they were only able to see colors indeterminately. Yet, when we come to these determinations that change the structures of our awareness, they begin as horizons giving us preformed “new regions in the total world.” 24 It is true that after their acquisition, the older structures are destroyed. However, this process is one of bringing out something already implicit in the previous structures of 21 PP, p. 24/17. PP, p. 25/17. 23 PP, p. 38/30. 24 Ibid. 22 189 consciousness. So, rather than suggesting an incoherence in the objects and in our consciousness, it instead attests to their continuous self-unity: It is precisely by overthrowing data that the act of attention is related to previous acts, and the unity of consciousness is thus built up step by step through a ‘transition-synthesis’. The miracle of consciousness consists in its bringing to light, through attention, phenomena which reestablish the unity of the object in a new dimension at the very moment when they destroy it. 25 3. Synaesthetic Integration All implicitly and explicitly perceived phenomenal objects of our world, then, are like threads woven together through the integrating “fabric” of our body. 26 It gives the world a certain density or “thickness,” just as the tissues of our muscles or our skin are intermeshed so as to produce the thickness of our flesh. Moreover, perception, Merleau-Ponty thinks, must always involve an intermixing of all our senses. An object is then “an organism of colours, smells, sounds and tactile appearances which symbolize, modify and accord with each other according to the laws of a real logic […].” 27 The different sense qualities of the object are organically intertwined, because from the beginning, our body’s sense organs integrate their functioning to such a degree that we can find no sense-datum that is not conditioned by the others. It is not merely that one sense helps the others; rather, the impressions of one sense are found implicitly within the others, and all our impressions are intertwined with our bodily motions. When Merleau-Ponty contracts his foot, for example, he can see this motion in his mind even when wearing his shoes. 28 We also never actually see how our body looks when we walk, but we will recognize our gait visually when we see it filmed or if we watch it in our shadow. 29 So, our bodily integration was already there from the beginning: I do not translate the ‘data of touch’ ‘into the language of seeing’ or vice versa – I do not bring together one by one the parts of my body; this translation and this unification are performed once and for all within me: they are my body, itself. 30 Another way to articulate this sense-integration is that all sense-data are synaesthetic. He has us consider patients who lost the ability to visually perceive color qualities. Even without this capacity, they were still able many times to 25 PP, p. 39/30. PP, p. 272/235. 27 PP, p. 48/38. 28 PP, p. 174/149. 29 Ibid. 30 PP, p. 175/150. 26 190 determine the colors shining upon them, on account of how it was perceived in its mixture with the other senses. They might for example know it is yellow when their body responds as if feeling something stinging it; one patient said, “I clenched my teeth, and so I know that it is yellow.” 31 Of course even when we do visually perceive color qualities, we also sense them in these other ways as well. It is not that we first see red and then our body responds by enlivening itself; rather, just as soon as we see red, our body is enlivened at the same time, because seeing red is partly a tactile sensation felt throughout our bodies. 32 “Synaesthetic perception is the rule,” he writes, and the senses intercommunicate by opening on to the structure of the thing. One sees the hardness and brittleness of glass, and when, with a tinkling sound, it breaks, this sound is conveyed by the visible glass. One sees the springiness of steel, the ductility of red-hot steel, the hardness of a plane blade, the softness of shavings. 33 He has us consider that although we have two eyeballs with each one giving us different streams of visual data, we still have a unified view of one phenomenal world. He thinks that the visual quality of sounds and audible properties of colors come about through the same sort of synthesis of sense-data. Because all our senses are pre-integrated in this way, he says that their unity is an “a priori truth.” 34 Our body is “not a collection of adjacent organs, but a synergetic system”; their functions are all linked together in our actions. 35 4. Immersive and Sympathetic Integrations with the World When a child reaches out for something, from the beginning she feels herself a part of the world around her, because on that basis she knows that her body could move among the things around her and take them into her grasp. Our integration with the world, then, is evident from the way our senses allow our body to immediately move around and interact with all the other parts of the world. 36 In fact, we even take up the objects around us and make them extensions of our own sensibility. Merleau-Ponty’s famous example is the blind man walking with a stick. When first beginning to use it, he might feel the stick making contact with his hand. Yet after a while, it becomes as though the end of the stick is his new point of contact with the objects around him. He no longer feels the contact between his hand and the stick but instead 31 PP, p. 244/211. PP, p. 245/211. 33 PP, p. 265/229. 34 PP, p. 255/221. 35 PP, p. 270/234. 36 OE, p. 1594/162. 32 191 between the stick and the ground or other things his stick is “feeling.” 37 We are inherently geared to be organically integrated with the objective world around us. The blind person’s awareness wants and tries to extend into its surrounding world. We use telephones to extend our voices and ears into distant places. Our gaze, Merleau-Ponty writes, is analogous to the blind man’s stick: like his cane, our vision feels out the world in an interrogative way, ranging over objects and dwelling on them. This is “the organic relationship between subject and world, the active transcendence of consciousness, the momentum which carries it into a thing and into a world by means of its organs and instruments.” 38 Our body’s immersion in the world is evident as well in its sympathetic relationships with it. Consider how when we hear a sound, part of our ear apparatus vibrates at the same frequency, in sympathy with the air’s vibrations. It is as though there were a place of crossing-over between the world and our body: “In the same way I give ear, or look, in the expectation of a sensation, and suddenly the sensible takes possession of my ear or my gaze, and I surrender a part of my body, even my whole body, to this particular manner of vibrating and filling space known as blue or red.” 39 He also has us think of the holy sacrament of communion. The bread is not only something sensible. As well, it is believed that when we ingest it, it communicates into us the “real presence of God.” Sensation is like this too. We are not only given an impression of the world around us, but enter into communion with the world by means of the sympathetic relation of that sensation. 40 When our hands are about to feel something smooth, they take up a certain “degree,” “rate,” and “direction of movement” appropriate for feeling that kind of surface, instead of the sorts of motion and readiness needed to feel something rough. 41 The smooth thing called out to our hands to tell them how it needed to be felt, so that even before making physical contact, the smooth thing in a sense placed itself upon our hands. So, we cannot say that we are the toucher performing the action, and the smooth thing is something passive receiving our action. The smooth object acts on us just as much as we act on it. The thing we sense begins as a “vague beckoning” whose call to us allows us to “synchronize” with it. 42 We “interrogate” the object “according to its own wishes,” which places us into a “pre-established harmony” and “kinship” with it, an a priori sort of pre-condition of organic integration with the world, necessary for us being able 37 PP, p. 177/152. PP, p. 178/152–153. 39 PP, p. 245/212. 40 PP, pp. 245–246/212. 41 M. Merleau-Ponty, Le visible et l’invisible, in C. Lefort (ed.), Œuvres, Paris: Gallimard, 2010, p. 1759; The Visible and the Invisible, C. Lefort (ed.), English trans. by A. Lingis, Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1986, p. 133. Henceforth abbreviated as VI, with French/English page numbers. 42 PP, p. 248/214. 38 192 to sense the things around us. 43 Our hands can “[open] upon a tactile world” when we are feeling the world from within them, but this also requires that our hands remain accessible to being already touched by the outside world, which informs them how to go about their touching. In this way, there is a “crisscrossing” of the touching and the tangible. By opening themselves up in this way, our hands incorporate themselves into the world they feel out; “the two systems are applied upon one another, as the two halves of an orange”: 44 Thus a sensible datum which is on the point of being felt sets a kind of muddled problem for my body to solve. I must find the attitude which will provide it with the means of becoming determinate, of showing up as blue; I must find the reply to a question which is obscurely expressed. 45 So, we might think of ourselves together with the world we perceive as being of one flesh. There is an intimacy between us “as close as between the sea and the strand,” 46 while yet we are still somehow partly our own selves; we do not dissipate into the flesh just because we are so much a part of it. Objects, he says, do not begin as selfsame things which we as seers come to view after we begin opening our attention to them. Instead we and the objects are involved in an intimacy, as if “the gaze itself envelops them, clothes them with its own flesh.” 47 5. Differentials in the Phenomenal World In Difference and Repetition, Deleuze characterizes phenomenal appearances as involving pure differential relations that present to our awareness some sort of a sign. To explain these passages, we will first look at how Deleuze reads Leibniz’s micro-perceptions as being infinitely small sub-phenomena that are describable in calculus terms as differential relations. Leibniz writes: when we perceive colors or odors, we are perceiving nothing else but figures and movements, but figures and movements so small, so varied, and in such great number, that our minds are not capable in their present states of considering them singly and distinctly. As a consequence we are not aware that our perceptions are composed of infinitesimally small perceptions of figures and movements. For example, when we thoroughly mix very fine yellow and blue powders, we perceive green; we are not aware that what we in fact perceive is only yellow and blue, very finely mixed. 48 43 VI, p. 1759/133. Ibid. 45 PP, p. 248/214. 46 VI, p. 1756/130–131. 47 VI, p. 1757/131. 48 G. W. Leibniz, “Meditationes de Cognitione, Veritate et Ideis,” in C. I. Gerhardt (ed.), Die philosophischen Schriften von Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, vol. 4, Berlin: Georg Olms, 1965, p. 426; “Reflections on Knowledge, Truth, and Ideas,” in Monadology and Other Philosophical Essays, English trans. by P. Schrecker and A. M. Schrecker, Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1965, p. 10. 44 193 Deleuze combines this notion of infinitesimally small perceptions with the vanishing infinitesimals in Leibniz’s differential calculus, and he illustrates with Leibniz’s triangle demonstration. 49 Fig. 7 Leibniz’ triangle demonstration of vanishing values 50 Leibniz describes a geometrical figure with two triangles sharing a common diagonal line [figure 7]. As this line moves to the right, one triangle increases while the other decreases. Yet, the sides of both triangles remain proportional, so the ratio of the larger one always indicates the ratio of the smaller one. This holds even as the smaller triangle’s sides diminish to the infinitely small. They have vanished, but their differential relation remains, still discernible in the larger triangle. 51 49 G. Deleuze, Seminar 22/04/1980, English trans. by C. Stivale, http://www.webdeleuze.com, accessed 14-Dec2011. 50 G. W. Leibniz, Mathematische Schriften, vol. 4: Briefwechsel zwischen Leibniz, Wallis, Varignon, Guido Grandi, Zendrini, Hermann und Freiherrn von Tschirnhaus, C. I. Gerhardt (ed.), Halle: H. W. Schmidt, 1859; image taken from the pdf available at Archive.org, http://www.archive.org/details/leibnizensmathe02leibgoog, accessed 14-Dec-2011. 51 G. W. Leibniz, “Justification du calcul des infinitesimales par celuy de l’algebre ordinaire,” in C. I. Gerhardt (ed.), Mathematische Schriften, vol. 4: Briefwechsel zwischen Leibniz, Wallis, Varignon, Guido Grandi, Zendrini, Hermann und Freiherrn von Tschirnhaus, Hildesheim: Olms, 1971, pp. 104–106; “Justification of the Infinitesimal Calculus by That of Ordinary Algebra,” in L. E. Loemker (ed.), Philosophical Papers and Letters, English trans. by L. E. Loemker, Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1965, p. 545–546. 194 Fig. 8 The vanishing ratio remains displayed in the larger triangle So according to Deleuze’s reading, when we perceive green, we are really noticing the differential relations between infinitely small perceptions of blue and yellow. 52 At their basis, all our perceptions are primarily these undetectable micro-perceptions. Thus, the perception of green is not really the homogenizing blending of yellow and blue. Green results not from their assimilation and bleeding into one another, but rather from their differentially jarring up against each other. And neither the micro-perceptions of yellow nor those of blue have green on their phenomenal horizon. Thus, the whole is not implied in the parts. So contrary to Merleau-Ponty’s theory, phenomena in the world around us, for Deleuze, appear to our perception not when they integrate holistically, but rather when they oppose each other differentially. The micro-perceptions are obscure and confused; we perceive nothing in them, and yet they are like raw phenomenal data that is only secondarily synthesized into constituted perceptions. So, when the infinitely small perceptions of yellow and blue differentially relate to produce a higher-order phenomenon of green, our perception comes more into clarity, because we can better notice the color that we are seeing. As higher and higher orders differentially relate, the perceptions find themselves having greater clarity; thus, “clarity emerges from obscurity by way of a genetic process.” 53 The differential 52 G. Deleuze, Le pli. Leibniz et le Baroque, Paris: Les éditions de minuit, 1988, p. 119; The Fold: Leibniz and the Baroque, English trans. by T. Conley, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1993, p. 90. Henceforth abbreviated as P, with French/English page numbers. 53 P, p.120/90. 195 relating that produces the higher-order phenomenon in a sense is like a clarity filter, and there is an infinity of these filters. Each filter determines which perceptions will differentially relate so to produce higher-order phenomena on the basis of what is remarkable or notable in that perceptual situation. To use Gregory Bateson’s formulation, it is a matter of differences that make a difference. 54 Leibniz gives the example of the noisy sound from a mill or waterfall that we have become overly accustomed to. Perhaps at first the micro-perceptions of the sound were remarkable or notable when we initially began living near the waterfall. The first perceptual filter selects the micro-perceptions whose differential relations will provide a clearer perception of the sound. These various sub-perceptions are differentially related yet again and filtered to an even clearer perception, until reaching the highest order of clarity, the waterfall sound that we notice explicitly. However, because the sound is monotonous, the noise gradually becomes less remarkable, and other differential variations in our field of perception come to be selected instead through differential filtering. 55 By selecting what is remarkable, the perceptions become distinguished but not yet distinct. A perception obtains distinctness by means of yet another sort of filter that renders what is remarkable into what is regular. 56 This regularizing of the perceptions is perhaps what makes them less noticeable or phenomenal. So in the case of the waterfall sound, we at first distinguish its variations from all the other possible ones that could have differentially related so to come into clarity in our awareness. We hear it as its own perception, but as long as it stands out to us in its remarkableness, it seems new and heterogeneous each moment and still worthy of our attention. Yet, as we gradually realize that it has, for example, a certain range of volume that it never strays from, and the sorts of sounds it makes and their patterns also stay within certain ranges of variation, the perception then becomes regular and homogeneous. Our perception of the waterfall begins with a chaos of varying tiny sounds that demand our attention, but it all gradually turns into a blanket of ignorable white noise that occupies the background of our awareness. For Deleuze, the differential relation between micro-perceptions does not just hold for all the perceptual data given together in one instant, like all the micro-perceptions of blue and yellow that we have when seeing the green of an apple; rather, “tiny perceptions are as much the passage from one perception to another as they are components of each perception.”57 This is because 54 G. Bateson, Mind and Nature: A Necessary Unity, London: Wildwood House, 1979, p. 110. G. W. Leibniz, Nouveaux essais sur l’entendement humain, in C. I. Gerhardt (ed.), Die philosophischen Schriften, vol. 5, Berlin: Weidmann, 1882, p. 47; New Essays on Human Understanding, English trans. by P. Remnant and J. Bennett, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981, pp. 53–54, and see also P, pp. 116– 117/86. Deleuze uses the example of a watermill in his analysis. 56 P, p. 121/91. 57 P, p. 115/87. 55 196 in a way, the future is already sensed now in the immediate field of micro-perceptions. Following his waves illustration, Leibniz writes: the loudest noise in the world would never waken us if we did not have some perception of its start, which is small, just as the strongest force in the world would never break a rope unless the least force strained it and stretched it slightly, even though that little lengthening which is produced is imperceptible. 58 Deleuze reads this to mean that what we perceive now gives us tiny indications of what is to come. However abruptly I may flog my dog who eats his meal, the animal will have experienced the minute perceptions of my stealthy arrival on tiptoes, my hostile odor, and my lifting of the rod that subtend the conversion of pleasure into pain. How could a feeling of hunger follow one of satisfaction if a thousand tiny, elementary forms of hunger (for salts, for sugar, butter, etc.) were not released at diverse and indiscernible rhythms? 59 So like animals, we feel “pricklings,” even though what we will come to perceive is not yet clear to us. These are tiny perceptions that “are not integrated into present perception.” 60 In the following moments, more of these tiny pricklings prove remarkable and come out as a clear and distinguished perception. 61 These subversive micro-perceptions “destabilize the preceding macroperception while preparing the following one.” 62 This is strikingly similar to Merleau-Ponty’s notion that we now are implicitly aware of the content of our forthcoming perceptions. We should emphasize that for Deleuze, the basis for the implicit perception is not that future macro-perceptions are integrated with present ones, but rather that present ones are heterogeneous multiplicities with anti-integrational parts that overthrow former phenomenal appearings rather than blending them together. It is only on the highest order of synthesis, the regularizing filter that makes perceptions regular and homogeneous, that such a blending happens. So recall how a macro-perception is the differential product of sub-phenomena, which themselves are differentials of yet smaller ones, all the way to the infinitely small. We will turn now to Deleuze’s explicit discussions of phenomena in Difference and Repetition, and note how his modification of the J.-H. Rosny energetics formula corresponds to the analysis of Leibnizian micro-perceptions: 58 G. W. Leibniz, Nouveaux essais, op. cit., p. 47; New Essays, op. cit., p. 54. P, p. 115/87. 60 P, p. 116/87. 61 Ibid. 62 P, p. 115/87. 59 197 Every intensity is an E - E′, where each E refers to an e - e′, and e to ε - ε′ etc.: each intensity is already a coupling (in which each element of the couple refers in turn to couples of elements of another order), thereby revealing the qualitative content of quantity. We call this state of infinitely doubled difference which resonates to infinity disparity. Disparity – in other words, difference or intensity (difference of intensity) – is the sufficient reason of all phenomena, the condition of that which appears.63 Phenomena, Deleuze explains, flash in signal-sign systems, which we will illustrate with the orders of perception. When the system itself has at least two heterogeneous series – “two disparate orders capable of entering into communication” – then it is a signal. 64 Consider, for example, the sub-phenomenal and the macro-phenomenal levels. The phenomenon that flashes across this system, bringing about the communication between disparate series, is a sign. […] Every phenomenon is composite because not only are the two series which bound it heterogeneous but each is itself composed of heterogeneous terms, subtended by heterogeneous series which form so many sub-phenomena. 65 The green flashes out as the differential relation between yellow and blue, which themselves are differential relations, and so on to infinity. Green flashed out phenomenally because it was remarkable in that situation, and perhaps that is why we might call it a sign in Deleuze’s sense of the term here. The sound of the waterfall does not representationally signify anything when it flashes out, but it alerts our awareness to something remarkable in our phenomenal world. 6. Bodily Differentials Deleuze also uses Leibniz’s diagram when discussing Spinoza’s bodily affection, which will allow us to explain the anti-integrative relations between both our body and its world and also those within the Deleuzian phenomenal body itself. To do so, we begin with his interpretation of Spinoza’s simplest bodies so as to link his renditions of Spinozistic bodily composition and affective variation. 63 G. Deleuze, Différence et repetition, Paris: PUF, 1968, p. 287; Difference and Repetition, English trans. by P. Patton, New York: Columbia University Press, p. 222. Henceforth abbreviated as DR, with French/English page numbers. Rosny’s original formulation does not have the third coupling ε - ε′. Deleuze adds it, perhaps to emphasize that the orders go on to infinity. See J.-H. Rosny, Les sciences et le pluralisme, Paris: Félix Alcan, 1922, p. 6. 64 DR, p. 286/222. 65 Ibid. 198 Nested within the second book of Spinoza’s Ethics is a section known as “The Short Treatise on Physics,” where Spinoza explains the composition of compound bodies. On the most fundamental level, bodies are composed of simplest bodies, which are distinguishable from one another only on the basis of their differences in speeds and slownesses. 66 However, simplest bodies are not atoms for Spinoza. By means of his novel interpretations of Spinoza’s 12th and 32nd letters, the “Letter on Infinity” and the “Letter on Blood,” Deleuze characterizes these simplest bodies as pure differential relations, even though the letters predate the invention of differential calculus. 67 And it is also on this basis that Deleuze portrays Spinozistic bodily composition as being based on difference rather than on integration, despite Spinoza’s language suggesting otherwise. Spinoza writes that simplest bodies become “reciprocally united to each other” when “they are in reciprocal contact with each other, or if they are moved with the same or different degrees of speed in such a way that they communicate their motions to each other in some fixed ratio.” 68 However, this “fixed ratio” for Deleuze is a relation of continuous co-variation. What makes the relation fixed is not that it stays the same, but rather that the simplest bodies adaptively co-vary so that they may together maintain themselves as a compound despite each one affectively altering the other. To explain, Deleuze turns to Spinoza’s “Letter on Blood.” Here Spinoza writes about the particles of blood, which are the tiniest parts of “lymph, chyle, etc.,” using terminology similar to when he describes simplest bodies in the Ethics. Parts make up wholes when “the laws or nature of one part adapts itself to the laws or nature of another part in such wise that there is the least possible opposition between them.” 69 Deleuze takes into account that the simplest bodies are not atoms, and thus are not the basic indivisible extending bodies that make up larger extending bodies. 70 Instead, they are infinitely small partitions found together in infinite sets. According to Deleuze’s reading, when the simplest bodies of different sets continuously affect each other’s speeds and maintain their continuous co-modification, they compose compound bodies. And as well, the simplest bodies can be regarded as infinitely small vanishing terms whose differential value between their 66 B. Spinoza, Ethica, in C. Gebhardt (ed.), Opera, vol. 2, Heidelberg: Winter, 1972, p. 97; Ethics, English trans. by G. H. R. Parkinson, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000, p. 126. 67 S. Duffy, The Logic of Expression: Quality, Quantity and Intensity in Spinoza, Hegel and Deleuze, Aldershot: Ashgate, 2006, p. 48. 68 B. Spinoza, Ethica, op. cit., pp. 99–100; Ethics, op. cit., p. 128. 69 B. Spinoza, Epistolae, in C. Gebhardt (ed.), Opera, vol. 4, Heidelberg: Winter, 1972, p. 170; The Letters, English trans. by S. Shirley, Cambridge: Hackett, 1995, p. 192. 70 B. Spinoza, Renati Des Cartes Principiorum Philosophiae Pars I. & II., in C. Gebhardt (ed.), Opera, vol. 1, Heidelberg: Winter, 1972, p. 190; The Principles of Cartesian Philosophy, English trans. by S. Shirley, Cambridge: Hackett, 1998, p. 53. See also G. Deleuze, Spinoza et le problème de l’expression, Paris: Les éditions de minuit, 1968, p. 187; Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza, English trans. by M. Joughin, New York: Zone, 1990, p. 204. 199 speeds determines the compound’s power to affect other bodies and to sustain its differential composition under the influence of detrimental affections. 71 For example, chyle is an infinite set of very simple bodies. Lymph is another infinite set of the very simple bodies. What distinguishes the two infinite sets? It is the differential relation! You have this time a dy/dx which is: the infinitely small parts of chyle over the infinitely small parts of lymph, and this differential relation tends towards a limit: the blood, that is to say: chyle and lymph compose blood. 72 Our blood, then, is a “fixed ratio” only in the sense that the lymph and chyle maintain their continuously varying differential relation instead of splitting apart and forming differential relations with other bodies; in other words, their being related in a ratio remains fixed, even though the value of that ratio is under continuous alteration. Yet, the blood will decompose under the affective influence of arsenic, for example. The poison’s simplest bodies have a differential value that, rather than allowing the arsenic to combine with the blood, instead causes the lymph and chyle to lose their co-variational relations and to then take up relations with other simplest bodies. 73 Note as well that the blood’s power to sustain itself is dependent on its differential relation to other parts of the body. The blood differentially relates with other tissues to make up organs, which themselves differentially co-compose to constitute the whole body. Our body is then made of various levels of differential composition, all the way down to the infinitely smallest level of pure differences without terms. So when we are affected, our body’s total level of power varies depending on whether the affecting bodies increase or decrease the power of our compounds’ ability to retain their continually altering relations. Arsenic, upon entering our body, decomposes the blood, which then decomposes higher layers of our composition, and so on, sending shock waves of disruptive affections throughout all the levels of our body. As Spinoza writes: “I understand a body to have died when its parts are so disposed that they maintain a different ratio of motion and rest to one another.” 74 As we will find, these compositional disruptions are matters of continuously varying affective intensities sweeping throughout our bodies and altering their power levels. So as to better understand the continuous variations of our body’s overall power or perfection, Deleuze returns to differential calculus concepts. We will need to conceive affections as though they are like instantaneous velocities; 71 G. Deleuze, Spinoza. Philosophie pratique, Paris: Les éditions de minuit, 1981, p. 47; Spinoza: Practical Philosophy, English trans. by R. Hurley, San Francisco: City Lights, 1988, p. 32. 72 G. Deleuze, Seminar 10/03/1981, English trans. by S. Duffy, http://www.webdeleuze.com and http://www.univ-paris8.fr, accessed 14-Dec-2011. 73 Ibid. 74 B. Spinoza, Ethica, op. cit., p. 240; Ethics, op. cit., p. 256. 200 they would be more like tendencies-toward-change that express themselves in a pure instant, and as such they are intensive quantities rather than extensive ones. 75 One way to visualize this is to imagine a ball tied to a string and swung around in the air. At every phase of its motion, its direction is continuously varying, so as to form a circle. Yet, if we cut the string, the ball does not fly off in a spiral, but rather moves in a straight line. This is because at every instant the ball is tending straight outward even though it actually moves circularly [figure 9]. Fig. 9 Ball spinning on a string This path that lies at a right angle to the string would also be a tangent to a circle’s curve at that location. For a curve moving in a somewhat more irregular path, finding its tendencytoward-change is more complex, and here is where we might use something like Leibniz’s method. We create a triangle on the basis of how the curve’s dimensions extend in a certain region. Then, as with Leibniz’s triangles, we slowly diminish the two triangle legs, and the third diagonal side gives us the tangent, which also tells us which way the curve is tending at that place [figure 10]. Fig. 10 Tangent obtained through vanishing values So in this way, as the triangle legs almost completely contract upon each other, the diagonal line gives us the intensive value of the tendency-toward-change. 75 G. Deleuze, Seminar 20/01/1981, English trans. by S. Duffy, http://www.webdeleuze.com and http://www.univ-paris8.fr, accessed 14-Dec-2011. 201 Then, on the basis of Spinoza’s correspondence with Blyenbergh in letters 18 through 24, Deleuze characterizes affections as being series of instantaneous affective variations.76 Blyenbergh would like to know how it is possible that our perfection, that is, our power of affection, is always altering, and yet our essence is eternal. Blyenbergh writes “nothing else pertains to an essence than that which it possesses at the moment it is perceived,” 77 which Deleuze reformulates as “there belongs to an essence only the present, instantaneous affection that it experiences insofar as it experiences it.” 78 Deleuze offers an illustration for how affections are continuous variations that are given as differential relations in the sense of instantaneous velocities. We suppose we are meditating in a dark room. When someone abruptly enters and turns on the light, our concentration is broken and we are blinded. We become aware that our power of affection has decreased instantaneously in a “lightning fast” alteration: “Two successive affections, in cuts. The passage is the lived transition from one to the other,” and we experience this transition as the “phenomenon of passage.” Every passage between affections is then “necessarily an increase of power or a decrease of power.” 79 So if we were instead feeling for our glasses in the dark, and then someone turns on a softer light, our power instantaneously increases. What we feel in that instant is the intensity of the change, and thus we are phenomenally aware from moment to moment of a continuous alteration of affective intensity. So, we see that the continuous variation of affection not only involves a series of discrete intensities, but is continuous like a curve or wave as well. Deleuze elaborates this when discussing the sequences of ideas that we have while being continuously affected. When bodies affect us, we obtain inadequate ideas of them. Deleuze says, “I look at the sun, and the sun little-by-little disappears and I find myself in the dark of night; it is thus a series of successions, of coexistences of ideas, successions of ideas.” 80 Corresponding to these ideas is the continuous variation of increase and decrease in our power of action. To illustrate, he has us imagine that while walking down the street, we suddenly encounter our enemy Peter, and the idea of him makes us afraid. Yet, just then we notice our friend Paul; we turn our attention to him and become empowered by his charm. As we transitioned from the idea of Peter to the idea of Paul, we experienced our power continuously increase. “In other words,” Deleuze says, “there is a continuous variation in the form of an increase-diminution-increasediminution of the power of acting or the force of existing of someone according to the ideas which she has,” and “this kind of melodic line 76 Ibid. B. Spinoza, Epistolae, op. cit., p. 137; Letters, op. cit., p. 160. 78 G. Deleuze, Seminar 20/01/1981, op. cit. 79 Ibid. 80 G. Deleuze, Seminar 24/01/1978, English trans. by T. S. Murphy, http://www.webdeleuze.com and http://www.univ-paris8.fr, accessed 14-Dec-2011. 77 202 of continuous variation will define affect.” 81 It is a continuity made up of a series of intensities. So to solve Blyenbergh’s objection, then, Deleuze explains that an existing mode like our body is something that continuously varies in power on account of its affections. Yet, what is eternal about our modal essence is the fact that it is a range of possible power levels that our existing body can have, and when our power dips below the lowest threshold of our range, our body ceases to express our modal essence and instead decomposes into parts that express other essences. So, even while our body continuously alters throughout its duration, the essence it expresses remains eternally the same range of intensive quantities. To further explicate the phenomenological value of Deleuze’s rendition of Spinozistic affection, we should note his distinction between “affection” (affectio) and “affect” (affectus). 82 An affection is the effect that colliding bodies have on one another, and these effects determine the compositional integrity of each affected body. When our own body is affected, the affection itself serves as a sign that makes us aware of how much power we have at that moment. An affect, however, is more like an instantaneous variation or tendencytoward-change. It tells us whether that affection is tending to increase or decrease our power, and how strongly it is doing so. Affects, then, serve as signs of the affection’s intensity. Since affections make us aware merely of our quantities of power, he calls them “scalar.” Affects, however, he considers “vector,” because they also indicate to our awareness the up or down direction of the affection’s influence on our power. If we regard the affection as a place along a curve representing an increase or decrease of power, then the affect would be like the tangent at those locations, indicating how strongly and in which direction the instantaneous variation is tending. 83 And because affections and affects are signs that we interpret immediately, they then involve a sort of phenomenal bodily awareness of the way things in the world appear to us when they affect our bodies. Deleuze elaborates this affective awareness in his interpretation of Spinoza’s first two kinds of knowledge. We obtain knowledge of the first kind through our reception of affective signs that indicate an increase or decrease in our levels of power. The sun’s particles shockingly strike our skin, and we become aware of whether and how strongly the sun is empowering or weakening our body. 84 The second kind of knowledge is more like “knowhow” (savoir faire). We might be under the continuous detrimental affection of a body that will decompose our composition if we do not adapt and maintain our differential relation with it. To illustrate, Deleuze has us consider a line in Dante’s 81 Ibid. Ibid. 83 G. Deleuze, “Spinoza et les trois ‘éthiques’,” in Critique et clinique, Paris: Les éditions de minuit, 1993, pp. 172–173; “Spinoza and the Three ‘Ethics’,” in Essays Critical and Clinical, English trans. by D. W. Smith, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 138–139. 84 Ibid. 82 203 Inferno: 85 “The rain makes them howl like dogs; with one side they screen the other; they often turn themselves, the impious wretches.” 86 Rain droplets are pelting a damned soul, disrupting the composition of his skin at that location and thereby sending shock waves of decompositional forces throughout the rest of his body. Yet, to maintain his constitution, the soul turns up a new side of his body that is more able to sustain the affections. He is aware of how the rain affects him, and he thus knows how to self-affectively alter himself so to maintain his differential contact with it. Our active self-affection and adaptive interaction with the world around us is what Deleuze here calls “rhythm.” He also offers the example of swimming through a powerful wave. When we collide with the wave, its affection begins to decompose our body. Yet, by self-affectively altering the arrangements of our own body’s parts, we may swim in conjunction with the wave and together form a larger composite body. 87 Deleuze suggests another illustration to explain more clearly how affective rhythm involves couplings of continuous affective variations. He has us consider a dual improvisation of a violin and a piano. On the one hand, each one needs to improvisationally choose its own development. Yet, the musicians’ decisions will influence how the other plays in concord with it. So, in order for both instruments to maintain their differential co-composition, they must make self-modifications that are differentially compatible with those of the other player. 88 7. The Phenomenal Body without Organs We will now draw an even stronger contrast between a Deleuzian phenomenological body and a Merleau-Pontian one, by applying Spinozistic affective rhythm to the “rhythm of sensation” in Deleuze’s more phenomenologically relevant text, Francis Bacon: The Logic of Sensation. We keep in mind that affections proceed as a continuous variation that on the one hand is made up of discrete instantaneous intensities, while on the other hand still forming a fluid curve or “wave” of sorts. Likewise, each figure in Bacon’s paintings presents a “shifting sequence or series” of intensive variations, causing the sensation to exist “at diverse levels.” 89 Deleuze then offers four problematic hypotheses to explain how sensation is a matter of differences of level, with the fourth being the “phenomenological hypothesis.” It regards the levels as being different do- 85 G. Deleuze, Seminar 24/03/1981, English trans. by T. S. Murphy, http://www.webdeleuze.com and http://www.univ-paris8.fr, accessed 14-Dec-2011. 86 Dante, The Inferno of Dante Alighieri, English trans. by J. Carlyle, London: J. M. Dent, 1900, p. 61. 87 G. Deleuze, Seminar 24/01/1978, op. cit. 88 G. Deleuze, Seminar 31/03/1981, http://www.univ-paris8.fr, accessed 14-Dec-2011. 89 G. Deleuze, Francis Bacon. Logique de la sensation, Paris: Éditions du seuil, 2002, pp. 41–42; Francis Bacon: The Logic of Sensation, English trans. by D. W. Smith, London: Continuum, 2002, p. 27. Henceforth abbreviated as FB, with French/English page numbers. 204 mains of the senses, with each one being integrated with the others in a Merleau-Pontian synaesthetic way; for example, when our eyes see the stomping hooves of the bulls in Bacon’s bullfighting paintings, our ears seemingly hear the noises they make. In this sense, the painter would “make visible a kind of original unity of the senses.” Deleuze rejects this and the other hypotheses, because they do not take into account the “vital power” of sensational rhythm.90 In simple sensations, he writes, rhythm “appears as the vibration that flows through the body without organs, it is the vector of the sensation, it is what makes the sensation pass from one level to another.” 91 Recall that the “vector” of the affect-sign is the intensity of the affection’s increase or decrease in value. Also, these affective intensities send shock waves of disruption throughout the body’s composition, causing it to decompose and recompose, in accordance with a “rhythmic” co-variation within and between bodies. So, Deleuze’s reading of Spinozistic affect will now help us better characterize the phenomenological value of his body without organs, for he writes that it is “an intense and intensive body. It is traversed by a wave that traces levels or thresholds in the body according to the variations of its amplitude. Thus the body does not have organs, but thresholds or levels.” 92 In Deleuze’s Spinozistic body, these intensive levels are precisely what causes our bodily composition to shift and change its arrangements, and the more rhythmically our body acts, the more it breaks down its normal organic divisions and relations to produce new functional relations between its parts. In other words, the rhythm of affection, just like the rhythm of sensation, pushes our bodies to the limits of its organization, tending it toward being a body without organs. We see this correlation as well in Deleuze’s notion of the indeterminate and temporary organs of sensation moving from place to place in bodies without organs. The exposed side of the damned soul in Dante’s Inferno is the point of contact where the pelting rain distributes its decompositional affective shock waves throughout him. By turning another side upward, he self-affectively sends within himself waves of affective alteration so to rearrange the relations of his body, and by doing so, he creates a new site of sensitivity to the external waves of affection. Because he continually twists his sides around, each new organ of sensation replaces the prior one, making all of them temporary and indeterminate. Likewise, Deleuze writes of the body without organs: A wave with a variable amplitude flows through the body without organs; it traces zones and levels on this body according to the variations of its amplitude. When the wave encounters external forces at a particular level, a sensation appears. An organ will be determined by this encounter, but it is a provisional 90 FB, pp. 45–46/30. FB, p. 71/51. 92 FB, p. 47/32. 91 205 organ that endures only as long as the passage of the wave and the action of the force, and which will be displaced in order to be posited elsewhere. 93 So by interpreting Deleuze’s body without organs in this Spinozistic language, we may better explain his explicit attack on phenomenology when he contrasts the body without organs to the phenomenological lived body: This ground, this rhythmic unity of the senses, can be discovered only by going beyond the organism. The phenomenological hypothesis is perhaps insufficient because it merely invokes the lived body. But the lived body is still a paltry thing in comparison with a more profound and almost unlivable Power [Puissance]. We can seek the unity of rhythm only at the point where rhythm itself plunges into chaos, into the night, at the point where the differences of level are perpetually and violently mixed. Beyond the organism, but also at the limit of the lived body, there lies […] the body without organs. 94 According to the “phenomenological hypothesis,” the lived body’s sense-organ domains are synaesthetically linked. To contrast it with the body without organs, consider a Bergsonian example that Deleuze sometimes evokes: a cow automatically recognizing grass. 95 The cow is able to recognize grass because its habitual behaviors have formed the motor equivalent of a general idea. In the animal itself, we find representations which lack only reflection and some disinterestedness to be general ideas in the full sense of the term: if not, how should a cow that is being led stop before a meadow, no matter which, simply because it enters into the category that we call grass or meadow? 96 A living being selects from a pool of differences the parts or elements that satisfy one of its needs. Thus, although each experience of grass is different, they are all grouped together, because they each satisfy the cow’s hunger. The cow then can dip its head mechanically and eat the grass, without an intense awareness of all the meadow’s variations that would distinguish one clump from another. Bergson illustrates a sort of dephenomenalization that happens as our bodies become more accustomed and integrated into our surroundings. I take a walk in a town seen then for the first time. At every street corner I hesitate, uncertain where I am going. […] there is nothing in one attitude 93 FB, p. 49/34. FB, p. 47/32. 95 See DR, p. 176/135; G. Deleuze, Cinéma 2: L’image-temps, Paris: Les éditions de minuit, 1985, p. 62; Cinema 2: The Time Image, English trans. by H. Tomlinson and R. Galeta, London: Athlone, 1989, p. 42. 96 H. Bergson, La pensée et le mouvant. Essais et conférences, Paris: Félix Alcan, 1934, p. 66; The Creative Mind, English trans. by M. Andison, Westport, Connecticut : Greenwood, 1946, p. 62. 94 206 which foretells and prepares future attitudes. Later, after prolonged sojourn in the town, I shall go about it mechanically, without having any distinct perception of the objects which I am passing. […] these accompanying movements are organized to a degree which renders perception useless. I began by a state in which I distinguished only my perception; I shall end in a state in which I am hardly conscious of anything but automatism. 97 Yet, suppose the cow sees what looks like grass, eats it, only to find that it has the plastic taste of artificial turf. Quite suddenly, what the cow is eating becomes remarkable, and it comes to the forefront of its awareness. The parts of its phenomenal world are not integrating, as its bodily domains of tasting and seeing are forced to work simultaneously in a disharmonious way. As well, the cow stops its habitual action of dipping its head to eat the grass and in that way loses its integration with its world, as though the world suddenly became foreign to the cow. Thus, eating grass stands out as a potently phenomenal experience when the cow’s horizons cease to integrate. “Rhythm” in the Francis Bacon text is the unpredictable varying of the waves of sensation that affect each bodily domain differently in such a way that the sense data cannot be processed, regularized, recognized, and thereby dephenomenalized. While this use of the term “rhythm” is surely quite distinct from the Spinozistic sense, we might note that even in this context, rhythm also serves to explain the varying differential relations within the body, within the world, and between the body and the world that are at work in phenomenal experiences. 8. Conclusion Merleau-Ponty’s integrationist model of the body would better account for the passive synthesis of phenomenal objects and for our body’s normal organic functioning at work in this process. Phenomena for him come to be constituted by means of horizonal integrations, unfolding over time and occurring on the basis of our body’s internal cooperations and its sympathetic interaction with a coherent world. Yet, as the examples of the waterfall and grass illustrate, the more that the component parts and moments of our perception integrate, and the more our senses agree on what they sense, and thus the more accustomed to the world around us our body becomes, the less phenomenally intense the experience is. Hence, the lived body of Merleau-Ponty is a “paltry thing” compared to the body without organs, for it is incapable of having intense phenomenal experiences. The body without organs “lies at the limit” of the lived body, because it is only when the lived body’s harmonious, 97 H. Bergson, Matière et mémoire. Essai sur la relation du corps à l’esprit, Paris: Germer Baillière et Cie., 1903, pp. 100–101; Matter and Memory, English. trans. by N. M. Paul and W. S. Palmer, Mineola, New York: Dover, 2004, p. 110, emphasis mine. 207 integrated functioning breaks down that it comes closer to being the phenomenal body without organs. Deleuze’s difference-based model, then, can be seen as compatible with Merleau-Ponty’s model, as long as we distinguish their explanatory purposes. MerleauPonty’s theory better accounts for the ongoing constitution of phenomenal objects, the familiar things in the world around us, while Deleuze’s theory better explains the intensity of any given moment of phenomenal experience. Thus, although Deleuze’s model in many fundamental ways contraposes Merleau-Ponty’s model, we need not regard it as a critique of phenomenology itself, but rather as a useful contribution to phenomenology’s pool of theoretical ideas. Corry Shores Vlierbeeklaan 38 3010 Kessel-Lo, Belgium corry.shores@hiw.kuleuven.be Works Cited Bateson, G., Mind and Nature: A Necessary Unity, London: Wildwood House, 1979. Beaulieu, A., Gilles Deleuze et la phénoménologie, Mons: Sils Maria, 2004. Beistegui, M., “Toward a Phenomenology of Difference?” Research in Phenomenology 30 (2000), pp. 54–70. Bergson, H., Matière et mémoire. Essai sur la relation du corps à l’esprit, Paris: Germer Baillière et Cie., 1903; Matter and Memory, English trans. by N. M. Paul and W. S. Palmer, Mineola, New York: Dover, 2004. Bergson, H., La pensée et le mouvant. Essais et conférences, Paris: Félix Alcan, 1934; The Creative Mind, English trans. by M. Andison, Westport, Connecticut: Greenwood, 1946. Boundas, C., “Translator’s Introduction: Deleuze, Empiricism, and the Struggle for Subjectivity,” in G. Deleuze, Empiricism and Subjectivity: An Essay on Hume’s Theory of Human Nature, English trans. by C. Boundas, New York: Columbia University Press, 1991, pp. 1–19. Bryant, L., Difference and Givenness: Deleuze’s Transcendental Empiricism and the Ontology of Immanence, Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 2008. Colebrook, C., Gilles Deleuze, London: Routledge, 2002. Dante, The Inferno of Dante Alighieri, English trans. by J. Carlyle, London: J. M. Dent, 1900. Deleuze, G., Différence et répétition, Paris: PUF, 1968; Difference and Repetition, English trans. by P. Patton, New York: Columbia University Press, 1994. –––, Spinoza et le problème de l’expression, Paris: Les éditions de minuit, 1968; Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza, English trans. by M. Joughin, New York: Zone, 1990. –––, Spinoza. Philosophie pratique, Paris: Les éditions de minuit, 1981; Spinoza: Practical Philosophy, English trans. by R. Hurley, San Francisco: City Lights, 1988. –––, Cinéma 2. L’image-temps, Paris: Les éditions de minuit, 1985; Cinema 2: The Time Image, English trans. by H. Tomlinson and R. Galeta, London: Athlone, 1989. 208 –––, Le pli. Leibniz et le Baroque, Paris: Les éditions de minuit, 1988; The Fold: Leibniz and the Baroque, English trans. by T. Conley, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1993. –––, “Spinoza et les trois ‘éthiques’,” in Critique et clinique, Paris: Les éditions de minuit, 1993, pp. 173–187; “Spinoza and the Three ‘Ethics’,” in Essays Critical and Clinical, English trans. by D. W. Smith, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1997, pp. 138–151. –––, Francis Bacon. Logique de la sensation, Paris: Éditions du seuil, 2002; Frances Bacon: The Logic of Sensation, English trans. by D. W. Smith, London: Continuum, 2002. –––, Seminar 24/01/1978, English trans. by T. S. Murphy, http://www.webdeleuze.com and http://www.univ-paris8.fr, accessed 14-Dec-2011. –––, Seminar 22/04/1980, English trans. by C. Stivale, http://www.webdeleuze.com, accessed 14-Dec-2011. –––, Seminar 20/01/1981, English trans. by S. Duffy, http://www.webdeleuze.com and http://www.univ-paris8.fr, accessed 14-Dec-2011. –––, Seminar 10/03/1981, English trans. by S. Duffy, http://www.webdeleuze.com and http://www.univ-paris8.fr, accessed 14-Dec-2011. –––, Seminar 24/03/1981, English trans. by T. S. Murphy, http://www.webdeleuze.com and http://www.univ-paris8.fr, accessed 14-Dec-2011. –––, Seminar 31/03/1981, http://www.univ-paris8.fr, accessed 14-Dec-2011. Duffy, S., The Logic of Expression: Quality, Quantity and Intensity in Spinoza, Hegel and Deleuze, Aldershot: Ashgate, 2006. Foucault, M., “Theatrum Philosophicum,” in D. Bouchard (ed.), Language, Counter-Memory, Practice: Selected Essays and Interviews, English trans. by D. Bouchard and S. Simon, Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1977, pp. 165–196. Hughes, J., Deleuze and the Genesis of Representation, London: Continuum, 2008. Lawlor, L., “The End of Phenomenology: Expressionism in Deleuze and Merleau-Ponty,” Continental Philosophy Review 31.1 (1998), pp. 15–34. Lawlor, L., Thinking through French Philosophy: The Being of the Question, Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2003. Leibniz, G. W., “Justification du calcul des infinitesimales par celuy de l’algebre ordinaire,” in C. I. Gerhardt (ed.), Mathematische Schriften, vol. 4: Briefwechsel zwischen Leibniz, Wallis, Varignon, Guido Grandi, Zendrini, Hermann und Freiherrn von Tschirnhaus, Hildesheim: Olms, 1971, pp. 104–106; “Justification of the Infinitesimal Calculus by That of Ordinary Algebra,” in L. E. Loemker (ed.), Philosophical Papers and Letters, English trans. by L. E. Loemker, Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1965, pp. 545– 546. –––, Mathematische Schriften, vol. 4: Briefwechsel zwischen Leibniz, Wallis, Varignon, Guido Grandi, Zendrini, Hermann und Freiherrn von Tschirnhaus, C. I. Gerhardt (ed.), Halle: H. W. Schmidt, 1859. –––, “Meditationes de Cognitione, Veritate et Ideis,” in C. I. Gerhardt (ed.), Die philosophischen Schriften von Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, vol. 4, Berlin: Georg Olms, 1965, pp. 422–426; “Reflections on Knowledge, Truth, and Ideas,” in Monadology and Other Philosophical Essays, English trans. by P. Schrecker and A. M. Schrecker, Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1965, pp. 3–10. 209 –––, Nouveaux essais sur l’entendement humain, in C. I. Gerhardt (ed.), Die philosophischen Schriften, vol. 5, Berlin: Weidmann, 1882, pp. 39–509; New Essays on Human Understanding, English trans. by P. Remnant and J. Bennett, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981. –––, Phénoménologie de la perception, Paris: Gallimard, 1945; Phenomenology of Perception, English trans. by C. Smith, London: Routledge, 1962. –––, “L’œil et l’esprit,” in C. Lefort (ed.), Œuvres, Paris: Gallimard, 2010, pp. 1585–1628; “Eye and Mind,” English trans. by C. Dallery, in J. M. Edie (ed.), The Primacy of Perception and Other Essays, Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1964, pp. 159–190. –––, Le visible et l’invisible, in C. Lefort (ed.), Œuvres, Paris: Gallimard, 2010, pp. 1629– 1807; The Visible and the Invisible, C. Lefort (ed.), English trans. by A. Lingis, Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1968. Montebello, P., “Deleuze, une anti-phénoménologie?” Chiasmi International 13 (2011), pp. 315–325. Olkowski, D., Deleuze and the Ruin of Representation, Berkeley: University of California Press, 1999. –––, “Philosophy of Structure, Philosophy of Event: Deleuze’s Critique of Phenomenology,” Chiasmi International 13 (2011), pp. 193–216. Reynolds, J., and Roffe, J., “Deleuze and Merleau-Ponty: Immanence, Univocity and Phenomenology,” Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 37.3 (2006), pp. 229–251. Rosny, J.-H., Les sciences et le pluralisme, Paris: Félix Alcan, 1922. Somers-Hall, H., “Deleuze and Merleau-Ponty: Aesthetics of Difference,” in C. Boundas (ed.), Deleuze: The Intensive Reduction, London: Continuum, 2009, pp. 123–130. Spinoza, B., Epistolae, in C. Gebhardt (ed.), Opera, vol. 4, Heidelberg: Winter, 1972, pp. 1– 342; The Letters, English trans. by S. Shirley, Cambridge: Hackett, 1995. –––, Ethica, in C. Gebhardt (ed.), Opera, vol. 2, Heidelberg: Winter, 1972, pp. 41–308; Ethics, English trans. by G. H. R. Parkinson, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000. –––, Renati Des Cartes Principiorum Philosophiae Pars I. & II., in C. Gebhardt (ed.), Opera, vol. 1, Heidelberg: Winter, 1972, pp. 123–230; The Principles of Cartesian Philosophy, English trans. by S. Shirley, Cambridge: Hackett, 1998. Wambacq, J., “Depth and Time in Merleau-Ponty and Deleuze,” Chiasmi International 13 (2011), pp. 327–348. –––, “Maurice Merleau-Ponty and Gilles Deleuze as Interpreters of Henri Bergson,” in A. Tymieniecka (ed.), Transcendentalism Overturned: From Absolute Power of Consciousness until the Forces of Cosmic Architectonics (Analecta Husserliana 108), Dordrecht: Springer, 2011, pp. 269–284. –––, “Maurice Merleau-Ponty’s Criticism on Bergson’s Theory of Time Seen Through the Work of Gilles Deleuze,” Studia Phaenomenologica 11 (2011), pp. 309–325.