www.fgks.org   »   [go: up one dir, main page]

"Email" is the e-mail address you used when you registered.

"Password" is case sensitive.

If you need additional assistance, please contact .

Enter the e-mail address you used when enrolling for Britannica Premium Service and we will e-mail your password to you.

Christianity

Faith and reason

Different conceptions of faith cohere with different views of its relation to reason or rationality. The classic medieval understanding of faith, set forth by Thomas Aquinas, saw it as the belief in revealed truths on the authority of God as their ultimate source and guarantor. Thus, though the ultimate object of faith is God, its immediate object is the body of propositions articulating the basic Christian dogmas. Such faith is to be distinguished from knowledge. Whereas the propositions that are the objects of scientia, or knowledge, compel belief by their self-evidence or their demonstrability from self-evident premises, the propositions accepted by faith do not thus compel assent but require a voluntary act of trusting acceptance. As unforced belief, faith is “an act of the intellect assenting to the truth at the command of the will” (Summa theologiae, II/II, Q. 4, art. 5); and it is because this is a free and responsible act that faith is one of the virtues. It follows that one cannot have knowledge and faith at the same time in relation to the same proposition; faith can only arise in the absence of knowledge. Faith also differs from mere opinion, which is inherently changeable. Opinions are not matters of absolute commitment but allow in principle for the possibility of doubt and change. Faith, as the wholehearted acceptance of revealed truth, excludes doubt.

In the wider context of his philosophy, Aquinas held that human reason, without supernatural aid, can establish the existence of God and the immortality of the soul; for those who cannot or do not engage in such strenuous intellectual activity, however, these matters are also revealed and can be known by faith. Faith, though, extends beyond the findings of reason in accepting further truths such as the triune nature of God and the divinity of Christ. Aquinas thus supported the general (though not universal) Christian view that revelation supplements, rather than cancels or replaces, the findings of sound philosophy.

From a skeptical point of view, which does not acknowledge divine revelation, this Thomist conception amounts to faith—belief that is without evidence or that is stronger than the evidence warrants, the gap being filled by the believer’s own will to believe. As such it attracts the charge that belief upon insufficient evidence is always irrational.

In response to this kind of attack the French philosopher Blaise Pascal (1623–62) proposed a voluntarist defense of faith as a rational wager. Pascal assumed, in disagreement with Thomas Aquinas but in agreement with much modern thinking, that divine existence can neither be proved nor disproved. He reasoned, therefore, that if one decides to believe in God and to act on this basis, one gains eternal life if right but loses little if wrong, whereas if one decides not to believe, one gains little if right but may lose eternal life if wrong, concluding that the rational course is to believe. The argument has been criticized theologically for presupposing an unacceptable image of God as rewarding such calculating worship and also on the philosophical ground that it is too permissive in that it could justify belief in the claims, however fantastic, of any person or group who threatened nonbelievers with damnation or other dangerous consequences.

The American philosopher William James (1842–1910) refined this approach by limiting it, among matters that cannot be proved, to belief-options that one has some real inclination or desire to accept, carry momentous implications, and are such that a failure to choose constitutes a negative choice. Theistic belief is for many people such an option, and James claimed that they have the right to make the positive decision to believe and to proceed in their lives on that basis. Either choice involves unavoidable risks: on the one hand the risk of being importantly deluded and on the other the risk of missing a limitlessly valuable truth. In this situation each individual is entitled to decide which risk to run. This argument has also been criticized as being too permissive and as constituting in effect a license for wishful believing, but its basic principle can perhaps be validly used in the context of basing beliefs upon one’s religious experience.

The element of risk in faith as a free cognitive choice was emphasized, to the exclusion of all else, by Kierkegaard in his idea of the leap of faith. He believed that without risk there is no faith, and that the greater the risk the greater the faith. Faith is thus a passionate commitment, not based upon reason but inwardly necessitated, to that which can be grasped in no other way.

The epistemological character of faith as assent to propositions, basic to the Thomist account, is less pronounced in the conceptions of Pascal and James in that these accept not a system of doctrines but only the thought of God as existing, which itself has conceptual and implicitly propositional content. Kierkegaard’s self-constituting leap of faith likewise only implicitly involves conceptual and propositional thought, as does the account of faith based upon Ludwig Wittgenstein’s concept of seeing-as (Philosophical Investigations, 1953). Wittgenstein pointed to the epistemological significance of puzzle pictures, such as the ambiguous “duck-rabbit” that can be seen either as a duck’s head facing one way or a rabbit’s head facing another way. The enlarged concept of experiencing-as (developed by the British philosopher John Hick) refers to the way in which an object, event, or situation is experienced as having a particular character or meaning such that to experience it in this manner involves being in a dispositional state to behave in relation to the object or event, or within the situation, in ways that are appropriate to its having that particular character. All conscious experience is in this sense experiencing-as. The application of this idea to religion suggests that the total environment is religiously ambiguous, capable of being experienced in both religious and naturalistic ways. Religious faith is the element of uncompelled interpretation within the distinctively religious ways of experiencing—for theism, experiencing the world or events in history or in one’s own life as mediating the presence and activity of God. In ancient Hebrew history, for example, events that are described by secular historians as the effects of political and economic forces were experienced by the prophets as occasions in which God was saving or punishing, rewarding or testing, the Israelites. In such cases, religious experiencing-as does not replace secular experiencing-as but supervenes upon it, revealing a further order of meaning in the events of the world. And the often unconscious cognitive choice whereby someone experiences religiously constitutes, on this view, faith in its most epistemologically basic sense.

For these voluntarist, existentialist, and experiential conceptions of faith the place of reason in religion, although important, is secondary. Reason cannot directly establish the truth of religious propositions, but it can defend the propriety of trusting one’s deeper intuitions or one’s religious experience and basing one’s beliefs and life upon them. These schools of thought assume that the philosophical arguments for and against the existence of God are inconclusive, and that the universe is capable of being consistently thought of and experienced in both religious and naturalistic ways. This assumption, however, runs counter to the long tradition of natural theology.

LINKS
Other Britannica Sites

Articles from Britannica encyclopedias for elementary and high school students.

Christianity - Children's Encyclopedia (Ages 8-11)

With some 2 billion followers, Christianity is the world’s most widespread religion. Christianity is based on the life, death, and teachings of Jesus of Nazareth. The religion has three main branches-Roman Catholicism, Eastern Orthodoxy, and Protestantism.

Christianity - Student Encyclopedia (Ages 11 and up)

The beliefs and practices of Christianity are based on the teachings of Jesus Christ. Christianity is divided into three main denominations: Roman Catholic, Eastern Orthodox, and Protestant. There are more Christians in the world (some 2 billion at the beginning of the 21st century) than followers of any other single religion. (See also Jesus Christ.)

The topic Christianity is discussed at the following external Web sites.

Citations

To cite this page:

MLA Style:

"Christianity." Encyclopaedia Britannica. Encyclopaedia Britannica Online. Encyclopædia Britannica Inc., 2014. Web. 22 Oct. 2014. <http://www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/115240/Christianity>.

APA Style:

Christianity. (2014). In Encyclopaedia Britannica. Retrieved from http://www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/115240/Christianity

Harvard Style:

Christianity 2014. Encyclopædia Britannica Online. Retrieved 22 October, 2014, from http://www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/115240/Christianity

Chicago Manual of Style:

Encyclopædia Britannica Online, s. v. "Christianity," accessed October 22, 2014, http://www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/115240/Christianity.

 This feature allows you to export a Britannica citation in the RIS format used by many citation management software programs.
While every effort has been made to follow citation style rules, there may be some discrepancies. Please refer to the appropriate style manual or other sources if you have any questions.
VIDEOS
IMAGES

Britannica's Web Search provides an algorithm that improves the results of a standard web search.

Try searching the web for the topic Christianity.

No results found.
Type a word or double click on any word to see a definition from the Merriam-Webster Online Dictionary.
Type a word or double click on any word to see a definition from the Merriam-Webster Online Dictionary.
No results found.
Type a word to see synonyms from the Merriam-Webster Online Thesaurus.
Type a word to see synonyms from the Merriam-Webster Online Thesaurus.
VIDEOS
IMAGES
  • All of the media associated with this article appears on the left. Click an item to view it.
  • Mouse over the caption, credit, links or citations to learn more.
  • You can mouse over some images to magnify, or click on them to view full-screen.
  • Click on the Expand button to view this full-screen. Press Escape to return.
  • Click on audio player controls to interact.
JOIN COMMUNITY LOGIN
Join Free Community

Please join our community in order to save your work, create a new document, upload media files, recommend an article or submit changes to our editors.

Log In

"Email" is the e-mail address you used when you registered. "Password" is case sensitive.

If you need additional assistance, please contact customer support.

Enter the e-mail address you used when registering and we will e-mail your password to you. (or click on Cancel to go back).

Save to My Workspace
Share the full text of this article with your friends, associates, or readers by linking to it from your web site or social networking page.

Permalink
Copy Link
Britannica needs you! Become a part of more than two centuries of publishing tradition by contributing to this article. If your submission is accepted by our editors, you'll become a Britannica contributor and your name will appear along with the other people who have contributed to this article. View Submission Guidelines
View Changes:
Revised:
By:
Share
Feedback

Send us feedback about this topic, and one of our Editors will review your comments.

(Please limit to 900 characters)
(Please limit to 900 characters) Send

Copy and paste the HTML below to include this widget on your Web page.

Apply proxy prefix (optional):
Copy Link
The Britannica Store

Share This

Other users can view this at the following URL:
Copy

Create New Project

Done

Rename This Project

Done

Add or Remove from Projects

Add to project:
Add
Remove from Project:
Remove

Copy This Project

Copy

Import Projects

Please enter your user name and password
that you use to sign in to your workspace account on
Britannica Online Academic.
Quantcast